Skip to main content

Moral Interventions

  • Chapter
Diplomatic Interventions
  • 378 Accesses

Abstract

Social science has assumed a distinction between empirical statements about reality as it is and normative statements about how the world ought to be. Realists who claim to work with the world as it is, also make this distinction. In this view, the empirical reality is one of power politics; thus neither moral principle, ethical action nor legal codification is ultimately important at the international level. In the absence of any overarching authority, states are guided by their national interest rather than moral principle. War is a brute reality and the attempt to introduce norms is a mere add on, growing out of a desire to alter the unalterable. However, if war is viewed as a social artifact, then its practice is no less permeated with moral and normative restrictions than more explicit moral or humanitarian efforts to limit it.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. For the latter argument, see: Michael N. Barnett, “The UN and Global Security: The Norm is Mightier than the Sword,” Ethics and International Affairs 9 (1995), 50; John Keegan, A History of Warfare (London: Hutchinson, 1993); Martin van Creveld, “The Persian Gulf Crisis of 1990–1991 and the Future of Morally Constrained War,” Parameters, 22, 2 (1992), 37–8; Neta Crawford, Argument and Change in World Politics: Ethics, Decolonization and Humanitarian Intervention (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002). See: Jutta Weldes, Constructing the National Interest (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999), for an argument that the national interest is itself a social construct.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Terry Nardin and David R. Mapel, eds, Traditions of International Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), p. 2. Nardin and Mapel’s edited volume provides an excellent overview of various traditions of international ethics. See also: Charles R. Beitz, Marshall Cohen, Thomas Scanlon and A. John Simmons, eds, International Ethics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); Ward Thomas, The Ethics of Destruction (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001); Stanley Hoffman et al., The Ethics and Politics of Humanitarian Intervention (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996); Jonathan Moore, ed., Hard Choices: Moral Dilemmas in Humanitarian Intervention (New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 1999); David Campbell, Politics before Principle: Sovereignty, Ethics and Narratives of the Gulf War (Boulder, CO.: Lynne Rienner, 1993); Karen E. Smith and Margot Light, eds, Ethics and Foreign Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Thomas Donaldson, “Kant’s Global Rationalism,” in Nardin and Mapel, Traditions of International Ethics, pp. 136–7. See also: Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1964), and Critique of Practical Reason and Other Writings in Moral Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1949). For a discussion of agent-centered deontological theory, see: Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), pp. 164–85.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Max Weber, Politics as Vocation (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1965).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Thucycides, History of the Peloponnesian War (New York: Penguin Books, 1954), Book I, para. 76. The realist description of Thucydides is an incomplete reading of the role of morality in the History. See: Hayward Alker, Rediscoveries and Reformulations: Humanistic Methodologies for International Studies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 59–60, APRS; Crawford, Argument and Change.

    Google Scholar 

  6. He contrasted the actions of Cesare Borgia, who created order in his state with ruthlessness, to the Florentines, who, in avoiding cruelty, allowed the development of such disorder that their acquisition was “destroyed.” Niccolo Machiavelli, The Prince and the Discourses (New York: The Modern Library, 1950), chs 17, 65.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (New York: Penguin Books, ([1651] 1980), ch. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Another angle is that morality is a private not a public concern, inappropriate for policy. From the perspective of the practitioner theorist, morality should not enter into international discourse, although it is possible for it to do so. The classical perspective denies the possibility of moral considerations in an anarchical system. There are broadly descriptive and prescriptive accounts of the absence of morality in international relations. G. Graham, Ethics and International Relations (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Reinhold Neibuhr, Moral Man and Immoral Society: A Study in Ethics and Politics (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1932), p. 91.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Nicholas John Spykman, Americas Strategy in World Politics: The United States and the Balance of Power (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1942), p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Henry Kissinger, American Foreign Policy, 2nd edn (New York: W. W. Norton, 1977); Hans Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, 6th edn (New York: Knopf, 1948, rev. by K. W. Thompson, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Neta Crawford, “Just War Theory and the U.S. Counterterror War,” Perspectives on Politics, 1, 1 (2003).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations (New York: Basic Books, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Mervyn Frost, “The Ethics of Humanitarian Intervention: Protecting Civilians to Make Democratic Citizenship Possible,” in Karen E. Smith and Margot Light, eds, Ethics and Foreign Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Janice A. Thomson, “Norms in International Relations: A Conceptual Analysis,” International Journal of Group Tensions, 23 (1993), p. 73.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Although justness was still linked to a cause ordained by God. For a discussion of the Islamic Just War tradition, see: Terry Nardin, ed., The Ethics of War and Peace: Religious and Secular Perspectives (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Torbjorn L. Knutsen, A History of International Relations Theory (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1992), p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  18. St Augustine, City of God (New York: Image Books, 1958), book 19, chapter 7.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Knutsen, A History of International Relations Theory, p. 18. See Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae (New York: Benzinger Brother, [1266–1273] 1947).

    Google Scholar 

  20. James Turner Johnson, Morality and Contemporary Warfare (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1999), pp. 42–4.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Prior to the Second World War, this meant that non-state actors, for instance, those resisting occupation, had no just cause for war. On the contrary, occupying powers were justified in employing force against persons or groups that had no political superior. This was at the core of Rousseau’s critique of the laws of war as formulated by Grotius. For an in-depth discussion of historical debates regarding the relationship between occupation and resistance, see: Karma Nabulsi, “Occupying Armies and Civilian Populations,” in Traditions of War: Occupation, Resistance and the Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 19–65.

    Google Scholar 

  22. A. J. Coates, The Ethics of War (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1997), p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Adam Roberts and Richard Guelff, eds, Documents on the Laws of War (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Geoffrey Best, War and Law since 1945 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), p. 45. See also the discussion of the role of peace movements in William C. Olson and A. J. R. Groom, International Relations Then and Now: Origins and Trends in Interpretation (London: HarperCollins, 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  25. C. I. A. D. Draper, The Red Cross Conventions (London, Stevens and Sons Ltd, 1958), p. 2. The numbers appear to be contested since Draper puts the number of deaths at 38,000 while the Encyclopedia of Britannica states the more conservative estimate of 29,000. See http://concise.britannica.com/ebc/article?tocId=9379057

  26. For further background on Dunant’s experience and the pamphlet, see: Pierre Boissier, From Solferino to Tsushima: History of the International Committee of the Red Cross (Geneva: Henry Dunant Institute, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Michael Burleigh, The Third Reich: A New History (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 2001), p. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Collective Security was not a new idea but one as old as the Westphalian System. Adam Roberts and Benedict Kingsbury, United Nations, Divided World: The UNs Role in International Relations, 2nd edn (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993), p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Articles 12–15 took up South African Jan Smut’s idea for a breathing space, during which war would be precluded as countries attempted to settle their disputes peacefully and public opinion would thus be allowed time to restrain any rush to war. Clive Archer, International Organizations (London: Routledge, 2001), p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  30. E. H. Carr, “The Beginning of a Science,” The Twenty YearsCrisis: 1919–1939 (London: Papermac, [1939] 1964), p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Thomas Weiss and Cindy Collins, Humanitarian Challenges and Intervention: World Politics and the Dilemmas of Help (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1996), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Larry Minear, The Humanitarian Enterprise: Dilemmas and Discoveries (Bloomfield, CT: Kumarian Press, 2002), p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Emergency and distress relief increased from $766 million in 1989 to 4.365 billion in 1999, OECD/DAC, Development Cooperation 2000 Report (Paris), table 2, 180–1.

    Google Scholar 

  34. For an analysis of UN powers under chapter VII, see: Danesh Sarooshi, The United Nations and the Development of Collective Security: The Delegation by the UN Security Council of its Chapter VII Powers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  35. Rights of due process, under the Third and Fourth Geneva Conventions of 1949, deal with prisoners of war and civilians respectively. The defendant has the right to be told—early on and in a language he understands—what he is accused of; to be presumed innocent until proven guilty; to be tried without undue delay; to be heard before an impartial decision-maker; to be tried in a “regularly constituted court” (if the accused is a PoW, it may be a military court); to prepare and present a defense; to present witnesses; not to be required to testify against himself or to confess guilt; to be tried in his presence; to be convicted only of a crime that he himself committed; not to be punished more than once for the same act; to be convicted only for what was a crime at the time of the act in question; to have a sentence no more severe than the law allowed at the time of the act in question; to be told of his rights of appeal and what time limits there are; to appeal and ask for pardon or reprieve; and to have any death sentence stayed until six months after notification of the protecting power. For a more detailed discussion, see: Gideon Levy, “Due Process,” in Roy Gutman and David Rieff, eds, Crimes of War: What the Public Should Know (London: W. W. Norton, 1999), pp. 127–30.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Adam Roberts, “Counter-Terrorism, Armed Force and the Laws of War,” Survival, 44, 1 (2002), p. 24. See also: Adam Roberts, “The Laws of War in the War on Terror,” Israeli Yearbook on Human Rights, vol. 32 (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 2002).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2005 K. M. Fierke

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fierke, K.M. (2005). Moral Interventions. In: Diplomatic Interventions. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230509917_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics