Skip to main content

Beyond the Limits of Reason: Kant, Critique and Enlightenment

  • Chapter
  • 332 Accesses

Abstract

In The Order of Things, Michel Foucault calls Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason ‘the threshold of our modernity’ and even says that it marks ‘a fundamental event — certainly one of the most radical that ever occurred in Western thought’.1 Taken out of context, these remarks sound like high praise. They are, however, part of a sweeping criticism of the historical development that made ‘man’ the privileged object of the human sciences at the end of the eighteenth century. According to Foucault, it was Kant’s critique that allowed the human sciences to fall into the ‘anthropological sleep’ that remains ‘a stubborn obstacle standing obstinately in the way of an imminent new form of thought’.2 For this reason, Foucault denounces Kant as the philosopher who had ‘stupefied Western thought, leaving it blind to its own modernity for nearly two hundred years’.3

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. M. Foucault, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences, translated by R. Hurley (New York: Vintage Books, 1994), 220, 242.

    Google Scholar 

  2. It should be noted that Foucault blames ‘the Kantian enigma’ rather than Kant himself for stupefying and blinding Western thought. See M. Foucault, ‘Une histoire restée muette’, in Michel Foucault: Dits et Écrits (I:1954–1975), edited by D. Defert et al. (Paris: Gallimard, 2001), 574. See also

    Google Scholar 

  3. M. Djaballah, Kant, Foucault, and the Forms of Experience (New York: Routledge, 2008), 3.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See M. Foucault, ‘What is Critique?’, in The Essential Foucault, translated by L. Hochroth, edited by P. Rabinow and N. Rose (New York: New Press, 1994), 268.

    Google Scholar 

  5. M. Foucault, ‘What is Enlightenment?’, in The Essential Foucault, 53 (hereafter WE). This essay was presumably written for a conference at Boston College, where Foucault had invited Jürgen Habermas, Hubert Dreyfus, Richard Rorty and Charles Taylor to discuss Kant’s essay. Unfortunately, Foucault died before this conference could take place. His essay was published posthumously by P. Rabinow (ed.), in The Foucault Reader (New York: Pantheon Books, 1984), 32–50.

    Google Scholar 

  6. J. Habermas, ‘Taking Aim at the Heart of the Present: On Foucault’s Lecture on Kant’s What is Enlightenment?’, in The New Conservativism: Cultural Criticism and the Historians’ Debate, translated by S. Weber Nicholsen (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 176.

    Google Scholar 

  7. M. Foucault, ‘Omnes et Singulatim: Toward a Critique of Political Reason’, in J. D. Faubion (ed.), The Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984, Volume 3 (New York: New Press, 2000), 298.

    Google Scholar 

  8. I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, translated by P. Guyer and A. W. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), Axi (hereafter CPR).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  9. QWE 17. Mary Gregor translates the famous first sentence of Kant’s essay (Aufklärung ist der Ausgang des Menschen aus seiner selbstverschuldeten Unmündigkeit) as ‘enlightenment is the human being’s emergence from his self-incurred minority’. Gregor’s decision to translate ‘der Ausgang’ as ‘emergence’ would have been problematic for Foucault, who emphasises that ‘Ausgang’ means ‘exit’ or ‘way out’ in his reflections on Kant’s essay. Yet ‘Ausgang’ can also refer to a beginning, a starting point or point of departure, as indicated by Gregor’s translation. The play of the various meanings of ‘Ausgang’ is important to the sense of Kant’s conception of enlightenment, which is not ‘wholly negative’ as Foucault sometimes claims. See WE 48. See also M. Foucault, The Government of Self and Others: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1982–1983, translated by G. Burchell (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), 27–28.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. H. Arendt, Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, edited by R. Beiner (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 39.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., 39–40. For Arendt’s view of the difference between the perspectives of the citizen and the philosopher, see H. Arendt, ‘Philosophy and Politics’, Social Research, 57/1, 1990, 78–82.

    Google Scholar 

  12. K. Deligiorgi, Kant and the Culture of Enlightenment (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2005), 72.

    Google Scholar 

  13. ‘A learned man,’ according to Kant, ‘is one whose learnedness is not grounded on common experience’ (Ein Gelahrter heißt, deßen Gelahrtsamkeit sich nicht auf gemeine Erfahrung gründet). The ‘learnedness’ (Gelahrtsamkeit) of a scholar or ‘learned man’ (Gelahrter) is instead based on the ‘universal cognitions of the understanding’, whose ‘universal rules’ constitute ‘science’ (Wissenschaft). This is to be contrasted with the common understanding that is ‘the understanding for judging according to laws of experience’. See, for example, I. Kant, Lectures on Logic, translated and edited by J. M. Young (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 6–7, 11–12).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  14. Many examples could be cited, because the narrative about Kant’s place in the history of modern philosophy has been institutionalised with amazing consistency. While this is no indication of the truth of that narrative, it is an important indication of how the history of philosophy is written. See, for example, R. Schacht, Classical Modern Philosophers: Descartes to Kant (New York: Routledge, 1984), 163–165;

    Google Scholar 

  15. F. Coplestone, A History of Philosophy, Volume VI: Modern Philosophy from the French Enlightenment to Kant (New York: Image Books, 1994), 211–212, 277–278; and

    Google Scholar 

  16. A. Kenney, A New History of Western Philosophy, Volume III: The Rise of Modern Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), 101–102.

    Google Scholar 

  17. The principles of the Transcendental Analytic are, according to Kant, ‘merely principles of the exposition of appearances and the proud name of ontology, which presumes to offer synthetic a priori cognitions of things in general in a systematic doctrine (e.g., the principle of causality), must give way to the modest one of a mere analytic of the pure understanding’. See CPR, A247/B303. While this passage is often read as a general substitution of transcendental philosophy for ontology, Karin de Boer has argued that Kant’s criticism of traditional ontology is more nuanced. See K. de Boer, ‘Transformations of Transcendental Philosophy: Wolff, Kant, and Hegel’, Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain, 63, 2011, 50–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. I. Kant, ‘Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics that Will be Able to Come Forward as a Science’, in Theoretical Philosophy after 1781, translated by G. Hatfield, edited by H. Allison and P. Heath (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 154.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See, for example, W. H. Walsh, ‘Philosophy and Psychology in Kant’s Critique’, Kant-Studien, 56, 1966, 191. See also

    Google Scholar 

  20. P. Kitcher, Kant’s Transcendental Psychology (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 10.

    Google Scholar 

  21. CPR, Bxxiii. See also A. Nuzzo, Kant and the Unity of Reason (West Lafayette, IN: Purdue University Press, 2005), 39.

    Google Scholar 

  22. M. Mendelssohn, Jerusalem, Or on Religious Power and Judaism, translated by A. Arkush (Hanover, PA: Brandeis University Press, 1983), 61.

    Google Scholar 

  23. For an important account of the ways in which Kant’s transcendental idealism and his moral philosophy might be consistent, see A. Nuzzo, Ideal Embodiment: Kant’s Theory of Sensibility (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2008), 123–125.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2012 Colin McQuillan

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

McQuillan, C. (2012). Beyond the Limits of Reason: Kant, Critique and Enlightenment. In: de Boer, K., Sonderegger, R. (eds) Conceptions of Critique in Modern and Contemporary Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230357006_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics