Skip to main content

Competing Universals: Liberalism

  • Chapter
A Whole New World

Part of the book series: Palgrave Studies in International Relations Series ((PSIR))

  • 149 Accesses

Abstract

Liberalism is the great Other vis-à-vis realism — the “historical alternative,” as Tim Dunne puts it1 — set out in counterpart to the traditional pre-eminence of the realist paradigm in international studies. The liberal literature is in fact in precise opposition to realism, so to say, because it reverses the most fundamental premise of realist thought. Realism assumes that violence precedes the emergence of rationality and society, and that the way in which it is handled and managed then determines the nature of both the rational and the social in human affairs. Liberalism, on the contrary, presupposes the existence of an intrinsic sense of rationality and sociability in humans, which exists aside from violence and therefore can limit its sway in the constitution and evolution of society.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 44.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 59.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Tim Dunne, “Liberalism,” in John Baylis and Steve Smith, eds, The Globalization of World Politics. An Introduction to International Relations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 163.

    Google Scholar 

  2. John Locke, The Two Treaties of Government [1689?] (Edited with an Introduction and Notes by Peter Laslett) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960), The Second Treatise, paragraph 19, p. 280 in this edition. Emphasis in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  3. The second edition of The Critique of Pure Reason, where Kant responds to the reviews addressed to the first version of the text, is the best known one. It was published in 1787. The Critique of Practical Reason was also published in 1787, and grew out of the revisions added to the Critique of Pure Reason. Idea for a Universal History from a Cosmopolitan Point of View was published in 1784, while Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch came out in 1795. The best compendium of all these texts is Lewis White Beck, ed., Kant: Selections (New York and London: Scribner/Macmillan, 1988). The subsequent excerpts from Kant’s texts are taken from this volume.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See for instance the argument defended in Lewis White Beck, A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason (Indianapolis: Library of Liberal Arts, 1960). Kant opens up the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason with a “Preface and Introduction” which itself starts with some thoughts on “The Copernican Revolution in Metaphysics.” See Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, in Beck, Kant: Selections, 95.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Wade L. Huntley, “Kant’s Third Image: Systemic Sources of the Liberal Peace,” International Studies Quarterly 40 (1996), 51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. On the importance of this question in Kantian studies, see for instance Steven B. Smith, “Defending Hegel from Kant,” in Howard Lloyd Williams, ed., Essays on Kant’s Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 280–286.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Kant, “On the Common Saying: ‘This May be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice,’” in Hans Heiss, ed., Kant: Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), 90.

    Google Scholar 

  8. David Boucher, Political Theories of International Relations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), 272.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Erik Gartzke, “Preferences and the Democratic Peace,” International Studies Quarterly 44, 2 (June 2000), 192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Jack Levy, “Domestic Politics and War,” Journal of Interdisciplinary History 18, 4 (Spring 1988), 653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. See also Jack Levy, “The Democratic Peace Hypothesis: From Description to Explanation,” Mershon International Studies Review 38 (1994), 352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. See Melvin Small and David Singer, “The War-Proneness of Democratic Regimes,” Jerusalem Journal of International Relations 1 (1976), 50–69.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See R. J. Rummel, “Libertarianism and International Violence,” Journal of Conflict Resolution 27 (1983), 27–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. See also R. J. Rummel, “Democracies Are Less Warlike than Other Regimes,” European Journal of International Relations 1 (1995), 457–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Erik Gartzke, for example, notes that “Oneal and Russett — together and with other co-authors — provide what is widely regarded as the leading quantitative research program in support of the democratic peace thesis.” Erik Gartzke, “Preferences and the Democratic Peace,” International Studies Quarterly 44, 2 (June 2000), 192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. On Oneal and Russett, see J. R. Oneal and B. Russett, “The Classical Liberals Were Right: Democracy, Interdependence, and Conflict, 1950–1985,” International Studies Quarterly 41, 2 (1997), 267–293;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. J. R. Oneal and B. Russett, “Is the Liberal Peace Just an Artifact of Cold War Interests? Assessing Recent Critiques,” International Interactions 25, 3 (1999), 213–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Michael Doyle, “Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 1,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 12, 3 (Summer 1983), 205–254;

    Google Scholar 

  19. Michael Doyle, “Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 2,” Philosophy and Public A ffairs 12, 4 (Fall 1983), 323–353.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See for instance Michael W. Doyle, Ways of War and Peace. Realism, Liberalism, and Socialism (New York and London: W.W. Norton & Company, 1997), 279.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Bruce Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace. Principles for a Post-Cold War World (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), 4.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See for instance Michael Doyle, “A Liberal View: Preserving and Expanding the Liberal Pacific Union,” in T. V. Paul and John Hall, eds, International Order and the Future of World Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 41–66.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See for instance David Held, “Democracy, the Nation-State and the Global System,” in David Held, ed., Political Theoty Today (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991),

    Google Scholar 

  24. and David Held, “Democracy: From City—States to a Cosmopolitan Order?,” Political Studies (September 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  25. The quote is from David Held, Democracy and the Global Order. From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1995), 227.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See for instance Richard Falk, “Global Civil Society and the Democratic Prospect,” in Barry Holden, ed., Global Democracy. Key Debates (London and New York: Routledge, 2000), 162–179,

    Google Scholar 

  27. and Richard Falk, “Global Civil Society: Perspectives, Initiatives, and Movements,” Oxford Development Studies 26 (1998), 99–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. More broadly, see Richard Falk, On Humane Governance: Towards a New Global Politics (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  29. Richard Falk, “Global Civil Society and the Democratic Prospect,” in Barry Holden, ed., Global Democracy. Key Debates (London and New York: Routledge, 2000), 165.

    Google Scholar 

  30. On the way in which Smith’s work resonates through later developments in liberal economics and their relation to the American capitalist spirit, see for instance E. Roll, “The Wealth of Nations 1776–1976,” Lloyds Bank Review 119 (January 1976), 12–22

    Google Scholar 

  31. and T. W. Hutchison, “Adam Smith and The Wealth of Nations,” Journal of Law and Economics 19, 3 (October 1976), 507–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Adam Smith, “The Theory of Moral Sentiments”, in The Works of Adam Smith, Volume 1 (Otto Zeiler, 1963). See part III, passim.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Glenn R. Morrow, The Ethical and Economic Theories of Adam Smith (New York: Longmans, Green, and Co. 1923), 31.

    Google Scholar 

  34. C. R. Fay, “Adam Smith and the Dynamic State,” Economic Journal 40 (March 1930), 28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. L. Billet, “The Just Economy: The Moral Basis of the Wealth of Nations,” Review of Social Economy 34 (December 1976), 303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Also see, for example, A. L. Macfie, “Adam Smith’s Moral Sentiments as Foundation for his Wealth of Nations,” Oxford Economic Papers 11 (October 1959), 209–228.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Edited and with an Introduction, Notes, Marginal Summary and Index by Edwin Cannan) (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976), Book IV, chapter II.

    Google Scholar 

  38. David Mitrany, A Working Peace System (Chicaco: Quadrangle Books, 1966).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ernst B. Haas, Beyond the Nation-State. Functionalism and International Organization (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1964).

    Google Scholar 

  40. Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Power and Interdependence. World Politics in Transition (Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  41. Robert O. Keohane, After Hegemony. Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Richard Rosecrance, The Rise of the Trading State. Commerce and Conquest in the Modern World (New York: Basic Books, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  43. See E. D. Mansfield and J. C. Pevehouse, “Trade Blocs, Trade Flows, and International Conflict,” International Organization 54 (2000), 775–808

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. and E. D. Mansfield, J. C. Pevehouse, and D. H. Bearce, “Preferential Trading Arrangements and Military Disputes,” Security Studies 9 (1999–2000), 92–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. See Bruce Russett and John R. Oneal, Triangulating Peace: Democracy, Interdependence, and International Organizations (New York: W. W. Norton, 2001);

    Google Scholar 

  46. John R. Oneal, Bruce Russett, and Michael L. Berbaum, “Causes of Peace: Democracy, Interdependence, and International Organizations, 1885–1992,” International Studies Quarterly 47 (2003), 371–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Erik Gartzke and Quang Li, “War, Peace, and the Invisible Hand: Positive Political Externalities of Economic Globalization,” International Studies Quarterly 47 (2003), 563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Michael Mousseau, “The Nexus of Market Society, Liberal Preferences, and Democratic Peace: Interdisciplinary Theory and Evidence,” International Studies Quarterly 47, 4 (December 2003), 489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2011 Pierre P. Lizée

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lizée, P.P. (2011). Competing Universals: Liberalism. In: A Whole New World. Palgrave Studies in International Relations Series. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230316843_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics