Advertisement

Man, the Explicit Animal

  • Michael Grant

Abstract

This reading, taken from The Explicit Animal (1991, 1999), addresses the question of what it is for human beings to be aware of themselves as human, which is inseparable from the question of how to characterise human consciousness. Man has repeatedly defined himself as a kind of animal, but one with special qualities, as an animal who in certain vital respects is not an animal at all. There is in effect an irreducible distance between the human and the animal and it is a distance that for Tallis derives from the fact of human explicitness. Man is the being who questions his own being. Man has been defined as the rational animal, the moral animal, the metaphysical animal, the tool-making animal, the spiritual animal, and so on. However, explicitness, or the power to make things explicit, is something deeper and wider than any mere faculty, such as reason. It is that in virtue of which the faculties themselves develop to the degree that they do. What makes us unique is the fact that we know what we are doing. Tallis makes it clear that the evolutionary explanation of the development of the human body is not in question; but none the less, he insists, the emergence of explicitness cannot be explained in terms of the Darwinian picture. He returns to his central point: the power of explicitness is sui generis, underivable. It cannot be reduced to anything else, nor can the existence of consciousness be explained. And to grasp this fact is to provide a further level of defence against the all too pervasive temptation to explain consciousness as though it were a machine.

Keywords

Human Language Human Consciousness Rational Animal Discriminant Behaviour Arbitrary Sign 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. 1.
    Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1967), p. 310.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Mary Midgley whose excellent Beast and Man. The Roots of Human Nature (London: Methuen, 1980).Google Scholar
  3. 4.
    For a discussion of this, see E.R. Leach, Lévi-Strauss (London: Fontana, 1970).Google Scholar
  4. 5.
    This view is developed in Madness and Civilisation. The madman, too, provided rational, civilised man with an image of his opposite, to iterate his sense of being rational and civilised. The connection between madness and animality in Foucault’s thought is well expressed by Alan Sheridan (Michel Foucault: The Will to Truth, London: Tavistock, 1980, p. 30):CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 7.
    Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, edited and introduced by C.J. Arthur (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1974), p. 42.Google Scholar
  6. 9.
    Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason, translated by Alan Sheridan (London: Verso, 1982), p. 260.Google Scholar
  7. 10.
    Karl Marx, Capital, vol. 1, translated by Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1970).Google Scholar
  8. 11.
    Richard Swinburne, The Evolution of the Soul (Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 2.Google Scholar
  9. 12.
    John Maynard Smith, The Theory of Evolution, 3rd edn (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1975), p. 311.Google Scholar
  10. 13.
    Lévi-Strauss’s views are accessibly summarised in E.R. Leach, Lévi-Strauss (London: Fontana, 1970).Google Scholar
  11. J.G. Merquior in From Prague to Paris: A Critique of Structuralist and Post-Structuralist Thought (London: Verso, 1986).Google Scholar
  12. 17.
    For example, Christopher Longuet-Higgins in a review article in London Review of Books: ‘Why are theoretical linguists so infernally sensitive about the linguistic uniqueness of homo sapiens?’ (‘Mental Processes’, 14 August, 1988, pp. 13–14).Google Scholar
  13. 18.
    George Steiner, Real Presences (London: Faber, 1989), pp. 53–4.Google Scholar
  14. 19.
    George Steiner, After Babel (Oxford University Press, 1975).Google Scholar
  15. 20.
    See Gabriel Marcel, A Metaphysical Diary (available in Being and Having, London: Fontana, 1965), pp. 47–63.Google Scholar
  16. 21.
    See Raymond Tallis, The Explicit Animal (London: Macmillan, 1991), Chapter 7.Google Scholar
  17. 22.
    Raymond Tallis, Not Saussure (London: Macmillan, 1988), ‘Reference Restored’ in this selection.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. 24.
    A.N. Whitehead, Science and the Modern World (New York: New American Library, 1925).Google Scholar
  19. 28.
    ‘The work of the philosopher consists in assembling reminders for a particular purpose’, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell, 1953), p. 50e.Google Scholar
  20. 29.
    B.F. Skinner, ‘The operational analysis of psychological terms’, Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 1984; 7:547–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 30.
    See, for example, Daniel Dennett, ‘When Frogs and Others Make Mistakes’ in The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford Books, 1987)Google Scholar
  22. 31.
    F. Nietzsche, ‘Truth and Lie in the Extra-Moral Sense’. This is available widely in numerous translations; for example, Geoffrey Clive (ed.), The Philosophy of Nietzsche (New York: Mentor, 1965), pp. 503–15.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Raymond Tallis 2000

Authors and Affiliations

  • Michael Grant
    • 1
  1. 1.Rutherford CollegeThe University of KentCanterburyUK

Personalised recommendations