Skip to main content

Literal Force: A Defence of Conventional Assertion

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: New Waves in Philosophy ((NWIP))

Abstract

The aim of this chapter is to motivate and defend a conventional approach to assertion and other illocutionary acts.1 Such an approach takes assertions, questions and orders to be moves within an essentially rule-governed activity similar to a game. The most controversial aspect of a conventional account of assertion is that according to it, for classifying an utterance as an assertion, question or command, ‘it is irrelevant what intentions the person speaking may have had’ (Dummett 1973, p. 302). I understand this to mean that it is irrelevant for the issue of whether an utterance is an assertion whether the utterer has certain communicative intentions, such as the intention to utter something true, the intention to get one’s audience to believe (that one believes) what one has asserted etc. Just as one can commit a foul in football without meaning to do so, one can make an assertion, issue a command or ask a question without meaning to do so. The rules of football specify that a certain form of conduct (tackling an opponent in a certain way), carried out under certain general conditions (being a member of a team engaged in a game of football) counts as committing a foul. Similarly, I claim, the rules of language specify that a certain form of conduct (uttering an assertoric sentence), carried out under certain general conditions (being a member of a speech community engaged in a conversation) counts as making an assertion.

But literal meaning may not (and in my view does not) go beyond truth conditions.

Donald Davidson (‘Communication and Convention’, p. 269)

Our difficulty arises from the fact that we have tried to characterize the activity of assertion without taking into account its being a conventional activity: the fact that a sentence expresses an act of assertion is as much a matter of linguistic convention as is its having the sense it has.

Michael Dummett (Frege: Philosophy of Language, p. 300.)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  • Alston, W. (2000) Illocutionary Acts and Sentence-Meaning (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. (1962) How To Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (2001) ‘You Don’t Say’, Synthese, 128, 15–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, S. (2004) Renewing Meaning: A Speech-Act Theoretic Approach (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, G. (1994) ‘Relevance Theory and Speech Acts’, in S. Tsohatzidis (ed.) Foundations of Speech Act Theory (London: Routledge).

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1983) ‘Assertion’, Nous, 17, 637–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (1999) ‘Normative Requirements’, Ratio, 12, 398–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1979) ‘Moods and Performancesí, in A. Margalit (ed.) Meaning and Use (Dordrecht: Reidel). Reprinted in his Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1982) ‘Communication and Conventioní, in D. Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1986) ‘A Nice Derangement of Epitaphsí, in E. Lepore (ed.) Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Blackwell).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1973) Frege: Philosophy of Language (London: Duckworth).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1993) ‘Mood, Force, and Convention’, in B. Vermazen and M Hintikka (eds) Essays on Davidson (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Reprinted in his The Seas of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  • Garc!a-Carpintero, M. (2001) ‘Gricean Reconstructions and the Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction’, Synthese, 128, 93–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garc!a-Carpintero, M. (2004) ‘Assertion and the Semantics of Force-Markers’, in C. Bianchi (ed.) The Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction (Stanford: CSLI Publications).

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnish, R.M. (1994) ‘Mood, Meaning and Speech Acts’, in S. Tsohatzidis (ed.) Foundations of Speech Act Theory (London: Routledge).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (1990) ‘A Note on “Languages and Language”’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 68, 116–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (1993) ‘Meaning and Evidence: A Reply to Lewis’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 71, 206–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kölbel, M. (1998) ‘Lewis, Language, Lust and Lies’, Inquiry, 41, 301–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, S. (1996) ‘A Chomskian Alternative to Convention-Based Semantics’, Mind, 105, 269–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1975) ‘Languages and Language’, in K. Gunderson (ed.) Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7 (Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press). Reprinted in his (1983). Page references to reprinted version.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979) ‘Scorekeeping in a Language Game’, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 339–59. Reprinted in his (1983). Page references to reprinted version.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983) Philosophical Papers (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1992) ‘Meaning Without Use: Reply to Hawthorne’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70, 106–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, J. (2004) ‘Fragments and Ellipsis’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 27, 661–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millar, A. (2004) Understanding People: Normativity and Rationalizing Explanation (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, P. (forthcoming) ‘Is Assertion Social?’, Journal of Pragmatics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, S. (2005) Contexts (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2004) Literal Meaning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumfitt, I. (1995) ‘Truth Conditions and Communication’, Mind, 104, 827–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadock, J.M. and Zwicky, A. (1985) ‘Speech Act Distinctions in Syntax’, in T. Shopen (ed.) Language Typology and Syntactic Description. Volume 1: Clause Structure (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1969) Speech Acts (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, G. (1990) ‘In the Mood for a Semantic Theory’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 41, 103–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. and Wilson, D. (1995) Relevance: Communication and Cognition, 2nd edn (Oxford: Blackwell).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. (1995) ‘Non-Sentential Assertions and Semantic Ellipsis’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 18, 281–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. (1997) ‘What Assertion Is Not’, Philosophical Studies, 85, 57–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. (1998) ‘Quantifier Phrases, Meaningfulness “In Isolation”, and Ellipsis’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 21, 311–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. (forthcoming a) ‘Neither Fragments nor Ellipsis’, in L. Progovac et al. (eds) The Syntax of Nonsententials (Philadelphia: John Benjamins).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. (forthcoming b) Words and Thoughts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (2002) ‘Common Ground’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 25, 701–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2000) ‘Context and Logical Form’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 23, 391–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2002) ‘Making it Articulated’, Mind & Language, 17, 149–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. (1964) ‘Intention and Convention in Speech Acts’, Philosophical Review 73, 439–60. Reprinted in J.R. Searle (ed.) Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1996) ‘Knowing and Asserting’, Philosophical Review, 105, 489–523. This article reappears in revised form as chapter 11 of his (2000).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000) Knowledge and Its Limits (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. and Sperber, D. (2002) ‘Truthfulness and Relevance’, Mind, 111, 583–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2010 Max Kölbel

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kölbel, M. (2010). Literal Force: A Defence of Conventional Assertion. In: Sawyer, S. (eds) New Waves in Philosophy of Language. New Waves in Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230248588_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics