Skip to main content

Liberty and Its Circumstances: A Functional Approach

  • Chapter
  • 294 Accesses

Part of the book series: New Waves in Philosophy ((NWIP))

Abstract

What is liberty? There are by now a number of familiar answers to this question. One such answer is that liberty consists in the absence of interference, in not being constrained against one’s will. Another is that liberty consists in self-mastery in the exercise of moral or political self-determination. A third is that liberty consists in the absence of arbitrary rule, in not being vulnerable to the whim of others. These answers can be seen as alternatives, among which you take your pick, refuting the others as somehow mistaken or wrong. This is reinforced, I believe, by the fact that definitions of freedom get to be associated with different ideological positions. Noninterference is “liberal” freedom,1 the absence of arbitrary rule is “republican” freedom, and the exercise of self-mastery or self-determination is perhaps “communitarian”, or “socialist.” Both the definitions, to put this starkly, and the ideological associations are, of course, simplistic and cover up a lot of variety. Unpacking that variety is not my concern here.2 Instead I will slightly shift focus and discuss the role played by the concept of liberty in our social and political theorizing. A general claim I wish to make is that the social world is too complex for any single one of these accounts to fill the part we seem to want “freedom” to play.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Andersson, Åsa (2007) Power and Social Ontology, Malmö: Bokbox Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth S. (1999) “What is the Point of Equality?,” Ethics, 109, 2, 287–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benn, S.I. and W.L. Weinstein (1971) “Being Free to Act, and Being a Free Man,” Mind, 80, 318, 194–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, Jeremy (1843) “On the Liberty of the Press, and Public Discussion. Jeremy Bentham to the Spanish People. Letter III. On the Liberty of Public Discussion in Free Meeting — Continuation from Letter II,” in John Bowring (ed.), The Works of Jeremy Bentham Vol. 2. Edinburgh: W. Tait.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, Isaiah (1969) Four Essays on Liberty, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flikschuh, Katrin (2007) Freedom: Contemporary Liberal Perspectives, Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallie, W. B. (1956) “Essentially Contested Concepts,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 167–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallie, W. B. (1964) “Essentially Contested Concepts.” in Philosophy and the Historical Understanding, London: Chatto & Windus, pp. 157–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldsmith, M. M. (2000) “Republican Liberty Considered,” History of Political Thought, 21, 3, 543–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halldenius, Lena (1998) “Non-Domination and Egalitarian Welfare Politics,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 1, 3, 335–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halldenius, Lena (2001) Liberty Revisited. A Historical and Systematic Account of an Egalitarian Conception of Liberty and Legitimacy, Lund: Bokbox Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halldenius, Lena (2003) “Locke and the Non-arbitrary,” The European Journal of Political Theory, 2, 3, 261–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halldenius, Lena (2005) “The Immorality of Emotional Response. Liberty and the Slavery Metaphor in Wollstonecraft’s Theory of Property,” in Å. Carlson (ed), Philosophical Aspects on Emotions, Stockholm: Thales, pp. 109–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halldenius, Lena (2007) “The Primacy of Right. On the Triad of Liberty, Equality, and Virtue in Wollstonecraft’s Political Thought,” The British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 15, 1, 75–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halldenius, Lena (2007a) “Liberty and Law. Institutional Circumstances of Freedom,” Redescriptions. Yearbook of Political Thought and Conceptual History, 11, 99–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, Sally (2000) “Gender and Race: (What) Are They? (What) Do We Want Them To Be?,” Noûs, 34, 1, 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas (1994 [1651]) Leviathan, Edwin Curley (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, Matthew H. (2001) “Freedom, Unfreedom and Skinner’s Hobbes,” The Journal of Political Philosophy, 9, 2, 204–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John (1988 [1689]) Two Treatises of Government, Peter Laslett (ed), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • MacCallum, Gerald (1967) “Negative and Positive Freedom,” The Philosophical Review, 76, 3, 312–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart (1989 [1859]) “On Liberty,” in Stefan Collini (ed.), On Liberty and Other Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart (1989 [1869]) “The Subjection of Women,” in Stefan Collini (ed), On Liberty and Other Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 117–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morriss, Peter (2002) Power. A Philosophical Analysis, Manchester: Manchester University Press, second edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip (1989) “A Definition of Negative Liberty,” Ratio NS, 2, 2, 153–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip (1996) “Freedom as Antipower,” Ethics, 106, 3, 576–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip (1997) Republicanism. A Theory of Freedom and Government, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip (2002) “Non-Consequentialism and Political Philosophy,” in David Schmidtz (ed), Robert Nozick, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 83–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip (2005) “The Domination Complaint,” Nomos, 46, 87–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel (1988) “Are Freedom and Liberty Twins?,” Political Theory, 16, 4, 523–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, Richard (1991 [1777]) “Additional Observations,” in D. O. Thomas (ed.) Political Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 76–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John (1971) A Theory of Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, Michael J. (1996) Democracy’s Discontent. America in Search of a Public Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. (1995) The Construction of Social Reality, Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. (2005) “What is an Institution?,” Journal of Institutional Economics, 1, 1, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simmons A. John and Christopher Heath Wellman (2005) Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin (1984) “The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives,” in R. Rorty, J. B. Schneewind and Q. Skinner (eds), Philosophy in History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 193–221.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin (1990) “The Republican Idea of Political Liberty,” in G. Bock, Q. Skinner and M. Viroli (eds), Machiavelli and Republicanism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin (1998) Liberty Before Liberalism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin (2002a) “A Third Concept of Liberty,” Proceedings of the British Academy, 117, 237–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin (2002b) “Hobbes on the Proper Signification of Liberty,” in Visions of Politics. Volume III Hobbes and Civil Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 209–37,

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles (1979) “What’s Wrong with Negative Liberty?,” in A. Ryan (ed.), The Idea of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 175–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard (2001) “From Freedom to Liberty: The Construction of a Political Value,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 30, 1, 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wollstonecraft, Mary (1989 [1794]) “An Historical and Moral View of the Origin and Progress of the French Revolution and the Effect it has Produced in Europe,” in J. Todd and M. Butler (eds), The Works of Mary Wollstonecraft, vol. 6 London: William Pickering, pp. 1–235.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2009 Lena Halldenius

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Halldenius, L. (2009). Liberty and Its Circumstances: A Functional Approach. In: de Bruin, B., Zurn, C.F. (eds) New Waves in Political Philosophy. New Waves in Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230234994_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics