Skip to main content

“Ocular Proof” and the Dangers of the Perceptual Faith

  • Chapter
Image Ethics in Shakespeare and Spenser
  • 92 Accesses

Abstract

Merleau-Ponty begins The Visible and the Invisible, naturally enough, by interrogating the notion that “we see the things themselves, the world is what we see.” Of such commonsense statements, Merleau-Ponty asserts that “if we ask ourselves what is this we, what seeing is, and what thing or world is, we enter into a labyrinth of difficulties and contradictions.”1 Rather than confront these difficult questions, the natural temptation is to retreat into the safety of what Merleau-Ponty termed “the perceptual faith,’ a belief in the existence of the material world ostensibly confirmed through the senses.2 In Othello, Shakespeare dramatizes how something like Merleau-Ponty’s “labyrinth of difficulties and contradictions” complicates the relationship of ethics and vision. The play specifically foregrounds the early modern struggle over the contradictory nature of vision as both the most direct conduit to the world as it is and the sense most susceptible to illusion and misinterpretation. In the following pages, I examine how Othello’s ethical failure stems in large part from his inability to understand the problematic relationship between vision and truth, and ultimately vision and ethics. If, as I argued in the last chapter, Measure for Measure represents one of Shakespeare’s most significant meditations on the conflict between codified morality and individual ethical decision making, in Othello the playwright turns his attention to the question of what constitutes an acceptable ground for moral judgment.

Trifles light as air

Are to the jealous confirmations strong

As proofs of holy writ.

Shakespeare, Othello, 3.3.322-24

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible, Followed by Working Notes, ed. Claude Lefort, trans. Alphonso Lingis (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1968), 3.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The first section of the first chapter of The Visible and the Invisible is entitled “The Perceptual Faith and its Obscurity” (p. 3). For a discussion of the emphasis on the material, see James A. Knapp and Jeffrey Pence, “Between Thing and Theory,” introduction to a special issue of Poetics Today 24.4 (2003): 641–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Martin Jay, Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in Twentieth-century French Thought (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1993), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  4. David Michael Levin, “Introduction,”, Sites of Vision: The Discursive Construction of Sight in the History of Philosophy, ed. David Michael Levin (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997), 7.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Patricia Parker, “Othello and Hamlet: Diktion, Spying, and the ‘Secret Place’ of Woman,” Representations 44 (Autumn, 1993): 60–95, esp. 65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd rev. ed., trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum 1995 [1960]), 261.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Philosophical Hermeneutics, trans. and ed. David E. Linge (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1976), 3.

    Google Scholar 

  8. For Gadamer’s place in this philosophical history, see Martin Jay’s “The Rise of Hermeneutics and the Crisis of Ocularcentrism”, Force Fields: Between Intellectual History and Cultural Critique (New York and London: Routledge, 1993), 99–113.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Stanley Cavell, The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), 482.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Robert B. Heilman, Magic in the Web: Action and Language in Othello (Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 1956), 58.

    Google Scholar 

  11. A. C. Bradley notes that while “the skill of Iago was extraordinary … so was his good fortune” (Shakespearean Tragedy: Lectures on Hamlet, Othello, King Lear, Macbeth [London: Macmillan; New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1960 {1904}], 182). Bradley points out that Bianca’s entrance and behavior are among the lucky breaks that go to Iago.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Heidegger locates the “coming into presence” of being in the visually inflected dynamic of concealing and revealing. One of his translators, William Lovitt, points out that this dynamic penetrated the philosopher’s reading, as in Heidegger’s appropriation of Heraclitus’s proverbial “nature loves to hide” as “concealedness is the very heart of coming into appearance” (Martin Heidegger, The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans, and intro. William Lovitt [New York: Harper and Row, 1969], 36n2). Again I want to emphasize that the visual is central to explanations of this epistemological difficulty.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Roland Barthes, S/Z: An Essay, trans. Richard Miller (New York: Hill and Wang 1974 [1970]), 81.

    Google Scholar 

  14. My argument shares something with Stephen Greenblatt’s assertion that the process at work in Othello is “a submission to narrative self-fashioning” (Stephen Greenblatt, Renaissance Self-Fashioning: From More to Shakespeare [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980], 234). I think it is important to add to Greenblatt’s reading, however, that the narratives that successfully produce the effect of submission are visually inflected.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Paul Ricoeur, “Explanation and Understanding: On Some Remarkable Connections among the Theory of the Text, Theory of Action, and Theory of History,” trans. Charles E. Regan and David Stewart, in The Philosophy of Paul Ricoeur: An Anthology of His Work, ed. Charles E. Regan and David Stewart (Boston: Beacon Press, 1978), 149–66.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Katherine Eisaman Maus, Inwardness and Theater in the English Renaissance (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995), 120. See Maus’s chapter on Othello for an extensive (and deeply learned) discussion of English jurisprudence.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, “Eye and Mind” trans. Carleton Dallery, in The Primacy of Perception, and Other Essays on Phenomenological Psychology, the Philosophy of Art, History, and Politics, ed. James M. Edie (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1964 [1960]), 189–90.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Heidegger’s turn to art has been attributed to his effort to atone for his participation in the promotion of National Socialism. On Heidegger’s role in promoting Nazi ideology, see Victor Farias, Heidegger and Nazism (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989);

    Google Scholar 

  19. Richard Wolin, ed., The Heidegger Controversy: A Critical Reader (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1998);

    Google Scholar 

  20. Emmanuel Faye, The Introduction of Nazism into Philosophy in light of the Unpublished Seminars of 1933–1935, trans. Michael B. Smith, foreword by Tom Rockmore (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2009).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2011 James A. Knapp

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Knapp, J.A. (2011). “Ocular Proof” and the Dangers of the Perceptual Faith. In: Image Ethics in Shakespeare and Spenser. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230117136_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics