Advertisement

Development as Human Well-being

  • Abbas Mirakhor
  • Hossein Askari

Abstract

The new institutionalism in Western economic thought was developed within the neoclassical economic framework, although it incorporated the modification of a number of neoclassical assumptions, including those regarding information, transaction costs, and, most importantly, rationality. Douglass North argued for the notion of bounded rationality first proposed by Herbert Simon who had noted that a critical assumption of utility theory in neoclassical economics was based on the improbable— that a rational individual is capable of large, elaborate, and, often, instantaneous calculations before making decisions. This assumption is needed to justify a further assumption that individuals, asconsumers or as producers, behave in a manner so as to maximize satisfaction and profits, respectively. Simon argued instead that, in reality, individuals operate within a “zone” of rationality rather than full rationality because of constraints. Consequently, both the power and the scope of rationality are bounded. As a result, rational individuals do not aim to maximizes atisfaction, but to find a limited-scope-zone of operation within which the individual turns over part of the required immense calculation to habits, rules, social norms, and customs, namely, institutions. Thus the individual aims to “satisfy” rather than to maximize utility. The assumption of bounded rationality allows individual behavior to be influenced by cultural values, norms and rules of behavior.1

Keywords

Gross Domestic Product Human Development Index Political Freedom Capita Gross Domestic Product Global Order 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. 1.
    R. Simon, Meccan Trade and Islam (Budapest: Akademiai Kiado, 1989).Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    M. Strathern, Reproducing the Future: Essays on Anthropology, Kinship and the New Reproductive Technologies (New York: Routledge, 1992), 124–112;Google Scholar
  3. J. Nelson, Economics for Humans, foreword to Reflections on Human Development by Mahbub Ul Haq, vii–xvi (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 3.
    M. Douglas and Steven Ney, Missing Persons (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1998), 22–24; Nelson, Economics for Humans, vii–xvi.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Ibid., 13–14, 20–21, 46; E. Durkheim, The Elementary Forms of Religious Life, translated by Joseph Ward Swain (New York: Free Press, 1995): 15–16, 265–267.Google Scholar
  6. 10.
    Mahbub ul Haq, Reflections on Human Development (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995): 3.Google Scholar
  7. 16.
    Amartya Sen, Development as Freedom (New York: Anchor Books, 1999), xv.Google Scholar
  8. 20.
    Ibid., 5–4, 18; M. Qizilbash, “Ethical Development,” World Development Vol. 24 No. 7 (1996): 1209–1221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 21.
    A. K. Sen, “Rational Fools,” in Choice, Welfare and Measurement, ed. A. Sen, 84–106 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1982); Sen, Development as Freedom, 271–272;Google Scholar
  10. Vivian Walsh, “Smith after Sen,” Review of Political Economy Vol. 12 No. 1 (2000): 5–25;CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. J. Halteman, “Is Adam Smith’s Moral Philosophy an Adequate Foundation for the Market Economy,” Journal of Markets and Morality Vol. 6 No.2 Fall (2003): 453–478.Google Scholar
  12. 27.
    R. Carmen, “Prima Mangiare, Poise Filosofare,” Journal of International Development Vol. 12 No. 7 (2000): 1019–1030;CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. D. Gasper, “Is Sen’s Capability Approach an Adequate Basis for Considering Human Development?” Review of Political Economy Vol. 14 No. 4 (2002): 435–461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 30.
    J. Cameron, “Amartya Sen on Economic Inequality, the Need for an Explicit Critique of Opulence,” Journal of International Development Vol. 12 No. 7 (2000): 1011–1045;CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. D. Gasper and J. Cameron, “Introduction: Assessing and Evaluating the Work of Amartya Sen,” Journal of International Development Vol. 12 No. 7 (2000): 985–988.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. 33.
    Peter C. Whybrow, American Mania (New York: W.W. Norton, 2005), 2–13.Google Scholar
  17. 37.
    T. Kasser and Richard M. Ryan, “A Dark Side of the American Dream,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology Vol. 65 No. 3 (1983): 410–423;Google Scholar
  18. R. F. Baumeister and M. R. Leary, “The Need to Belong: Desire for Interpersonal Attachments as a Fundamental Human Motivation,” Psychological Bulletin, 117 (1995): 497–529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 38.
    For the quotations from the Pope and additional presentation on his views see: G. R. Beabout and Edwards J. Echeverria, “The Culture of Consumerism,” Journal of Markets and Morality Vol. 5 No 2 Fall (2002): 339–383;Google Scholar
  20. Joseph G. Donders, ed., John Paul II, The Encyclicals, third edition (Maryknoll, NY: Or bis Books, 2005);Google Scholar
  21. A. Dulles, “Centesimus Annus and the Renewal of Culture,” Journal of Markets and Morality Vol. 2 No. 1 Spring (1999): 1–7;Google Scholar
  22. C. K. Wilbur “The Ethics of Consumption: A Roman Catholic View,” in Ethics of Consumerism, ed. D. A. Crocker and Toby L. Linden, 403–415 (New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998).Google Scholar
  23. 39.
    L. Weatherill, “The Meaning of Consumer Behavior in Late Seventeenth-and Early Eighteenth-Century England,” in Consumption and the World of Goods, ed. J. Brewer and R. Parker, 206–227 (London: Routledge, 1993).Google Scholar
  24. 40.
    J. Baudrillard, “Consumer Society,” in Consumer Society in American History: A Reader, ed. L. B. Glickman, 33–56 (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1999).Google Scholar
  25. 41.
    A. Cohen, A Consumer’s Republic: The Politics of Mass Consumption in Post-war America (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2003).Google Scholar
  26. 42.
    D. A. Crocker and Toby L. Linden, eds., Ethics of Consumerism (New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998);Google Scholar
  27. I. Princen, Michael Maniates, and Ken Conca eds., Confronting Consumption (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002).Google Scholar
  28. 44.
    Ibid., 4–6, 319–321; R. P. Hill, R. M. Peterson, and K. K. Dhanda, “Global Consumption and Distributive Justice: A Rawlsian Perspective,” Human Rights Quarterly Vol. 23 (2001): 171–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. 45.
    Princen, Maniates, and Conca, Confronting Consumption (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002), 322.Google Scholar
  30. 47.
    T. W. Pogge, “A Global Resource Dividend,” in Crocker and Linden, Ethics of Consumerism, 501–536; T. W. Pogge, “Eradicating Systemic Poverty: Brief for a Global Resource Dividend,” Journal of Human Development Vol. 2 No. 2001; T. Pogge, ed., Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Abbas Mirakhor and Hossein Askari 2010

Authors and Affiliations

  • Abbas Mirakhor
  • Hossein Askari

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations