Skip to main content

The Politics of Morality

  • Chapter
  • 106 Accesses

Abstract

Perhaps the best way to begin an inquiry into the relation between morality and politics is to start with an exploration of the nature of morality. This, in any event, is what I plan to do here, and when we turn to this issue, two seemingly contradictory aspects of morality quickly stand out. On the one hand, the notion of morality often seems to carry with it a sense of certainty, universality, and objectivity. To say, for example, that prima facie promises ought to be kept is to articulate a moral rule that is ordinarily supposed to be binding upon the will and in this sense true. The rule concedes that there may be some occasions when one ought not keep promises, but this is because there may be occasions when the rule is overridden by more urgent or pressing moral rules or principles. The rule does not assert, on the other hand, that it is simply true for some particular person at some distinctive point in time that promises ought to be kept. To say that a moral rule is objective is not to say that it is only true for some people at some point in time, though from a sociological point of view this is surely the case if the people in question believe the rule to be true. Instead, thinking some rule is objective implies that it is true tout court; the truth of the rule is not conditional upon the beliefs of those people who happen to ascribe to it. The idea of relativism, which may make some sense sociologically, seems inconsistent with our notion of morality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Cf. Richard Brandt, Hopi Ethics: A Theoretical Analysis (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1954);

    Google Scholar 

  2. John Ladd, The Structure of a Moral Code: A Philosophical Analysis of Ethical Discourse Applied to the Ethics of the Navaho Indians (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1957).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Kurt Baier, The Moral Point of View (New York: Random House, 1958), 126.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., 107. Baier’s moral point of view no doubt owes much to preceding ideal observer theories of morality, which, in turn, call to mind Adam Smith’s impartial spectator. Cf., Roderick Firth, “Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12 (1952): 317–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. For related arguments, see R.M. Hare, Reason and Freedom (London: Oxford University Press, 1963);

    Google Scholar 

  6. Alan Gewirth, Reason and Morality (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  7. See also J.L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (New York: Penguin Books, 1977), Ch. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, ed. J.P. Mayer, trans. George Lawrence (Garden City, NJ: Doubleday & Co., 1969), 526. Tocqueville actually uses the phrase “enlightened self-love” to describe what he calls self-interest “properly understood.”

    Google Scholar 

  9. See also David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Stuart Hampshire, Morality and Conflict (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983), 105.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Hampshire would seem to be in agreement with Baier on this point. He appeals to a process of reasoning, a process that involves hearing from and listening to others, in his thoughts on how to best address the problems created by normative conflict. Cf. Stuart Hampshire, Justice is Conflict (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000), 79–98.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Following this strategy, Kant regarded political philosophy as simply a special branch of moral philosophy. Cf., I. Kant, The Metaphysical of Morals, trans. by Mary Gregor (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 35–55.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Historically, this view of the relation of politics to morality, and of the social aspect of the moral law more generally, may be seen to emerge in the works of Pufendorf and Cumberland, both of whom took exception to the political realism of Hobbes and sought to strengthen the case for civil association by transforming this political realism into a form of moral necessity. On Pufendorf, see Craig L. Carr ed., The Political Writings of Samuel Pufendorf, trans. Michael J. Seidler (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994), 136–57. For Cumberland, see Richard Cumberland, A Philosophical Inquiry into the Laws of Nature (London, 1727).

    Google Scholar 

  14. See also Craig L. Carr and Michael J. Seidler, “Pufendorf, Sociality, and the Modern State,” History of Political Thought XVII, 3 (1996): 354–78.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Stuart Hampshire, Innocence and Experience (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), 177.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Machiavelli, The Prince, trans. Daniel Donno (Toronto: Bantam Books, 1981), 28–42.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cf. Stuart Hampshire, Two Theories of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), 44.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. Isaiah Berlin, “To Concepts of Liberty,” in Berlin ed., Four Essays on Liberty (London: Oxford University Press, 1969), 118–72.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., 186. Hampshire’s views in this regard are reminiscent of Rawls’s recourse to a shared public morality that underlies his attempt to configure his theory of justice in order to diffuse moral and normative conflict. This, in effect, is the spirit behind Rawls’s political liberalism; yet Rawls’s focus upon political stability pushed him in the direction of a pursuit of reasonableness that actually exacerbates the problem he hoped to address. Cf. John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 58–66.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2010 Craig L. Carr

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Carr, C.L. (2010). The Politics of Morality. In: Liberalism and Pluralism. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230106055_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics