Skip to main content

Gender, Just War, and Non-state Actors

  • Chapter
Book cover Ethics, Authority, and War

Abstract

The era of the “war on terror” has seen a sharp increase in the use of the rhetoric of good and evil in global politics.2 In the post-9/11 era, leaders in international relations and those who study their actions have channeled new attention toward the words and standards of the age-old tradition of just war.3 These standards, outlined in the first chapter of this volume, hold a high profile in international political discourse.4 Still, while some see the increasing use of just war words as a sign of the increasing salience of questions of ethics and war,5 others see it as a result of the vagueness and susceptibility to political manipulation.6 Indeed, if just war theories are the pulse of our understandings of the ethics of war, they are often a pulse that is difficult to keep track of and measure effectively.

1. I am appreciative to the editors of this volume for their careful and considered reading of my contribution. I also owe a debt to Amy Eckert, whose work has challenged me to think about non-state actors in just war theory through gendered lenses. Any mistakes remain my own.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Robert L. Ivie, “Rhetorical Deliberation and Democratic Politics in the Here and Now,” Rhetoric and Public Affairs 5 (2) (2002): 277–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. William J. Bennett, Why We Fight: Moral Clarity and the War on Terrorism (New York: Regnery Publishing, 2003).

    Google Scholar 

  3. See Michael Walzer, “Words of War: Challenges to the Just War Theory,” Harvard International Review 26 (11) (2004): 36–38;

    Google Scholar 

  4. Michael Walzer, Arguing about War (New York: Carnegie Council for International Affairs, 2004);

    Google Scholar 

  5. Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust War (New York: Basic Books, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Lewis R. Aiken, Morality and Ethics in Theory and Practice (Springfield, IL: University of Illinois Press, 2004).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Laura Sjoberg, “The Gendered Realities of the Immunity Principle: Why Gender Analysis Needs Feminism,” International Studies Quarterly 50 (4) (2006): 889–910;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Inis L. Claude, “Just War: Doctrines and Institutions,” Political Science Quarterly 95 (1) (1980): 83–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Laura Sjoberg, Gender, Justice, and the Wars in Iraq (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2006);

    Google Scholar 

  10. Neta C. Crawford, “Just War Theory and the U.S. Counterterror War,” Perspectives on Politics 1 (1) (2003): 5–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Jean Bethke Elshtain, ed., Just War Theory (New York: New York University Press, 1992), 268; Crawford, “Just War Theory and the U.S. Counterterror War.”

    Google Scholar 

  12. Sjoberg, Gender, Justice, and the Wars in Iraq; Sjoberg, “The Gendered Realities of the Immunity Principle”; Laura Sjoberg, “Why Just War Needs Feminism Now More than Ever,” International Politics 45 (1) (2008):1–18;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Helen Kinsella, “Discourses of Difference: Civilians, Combatants, and Compliance with the Laws of War,” Review of International Studies 31 (2005): 163–185;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Helen Kinsella, “Gendering Grotius: Sex and Sex Difference in the Laws of War,” Political Theory 34 (2) (2006): 161–191;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Helen Kinsella, “Understanding a War that is Not a War,” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 33 (1) (2007): 209–231;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Lucinda Peach, “An Alternative to Pacifism? Feminism and Just War Theory,” Hypatia 9 (2) (1994): 151–72. Though I did not know her well, this article of Lucinda Peach was the inspiration for much of my work trying to create an explicitly feminist take on just war theory, and was on my mind as I wrote this chapter. I was able to tell her that shortly before she passed away, and will always hope that my work in this area honors her memory.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Chris J. Cuomo, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence,” Hypatia 11 (4) (1996): 30–45; Elshtain, Just War Theory.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Sjoberg, “The Gendered Realities of the Immunity Principle.”; Fritz Kalshoven, The Law of Warfare: A Summary of Its Recent History and Trends in Development (Leiden: A.W. Sijthoff, 1973);

    Google Scholar 

  19. George Weigel, “From Last Resort to Endgame: Morality, the Gulf War, and the Peace Process,” in David E. Decrosse, ed., But Was It Just? Reflections on the Morality of the Persian Gulf War (New York: Doubleday, 1992), 20–43.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See, for early accounts, Elshtain, Just War Theory; Judith Stiehm, ed. Women’s and Men’s War (London: Pergamon, 1982);

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ruth Roach Pierson, “Beautiful Soul or Just Warrior: Gender and War,” Gender and History 1 (1) (1989): 77–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. There has been some controversy, of late, as to whether Jean Elshtain is, or ever was, a feminist critic of just war theorizing, largely resulting from the publication of her book, Just War against Terror: The Burden of American Power in a Violent World (New York: Basic Books, 2003), which argues for United States interventions in Afghanistan and Iraq using what many would characterize as antifeminist justifications. I have written on this question more extensively in Gender, Justice, and the Wars in Iraq, but note two points for the purposes of this chapter. First, I believe that seeing Just War against Terror as a radical shift for Elshtain relies on reading a normative agenda into her earlier work that I am just not certain was there. Second, regardless of Elshtain’s position on the just warrior/beautiful soul dichotomies and the resulting reading of just war theory as gendered, her observations of those phenomena inspired much feminist investigation of just war theorizing (including my own). As such, citation to this work is not only appropriate, but essential, regardless of the politics that either originally influenced her work or have come to influence it now.

    Google Scholar 

  23. V. Spike Peterson and Anne Sisson Runyan, Global Gender Issues (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1999), 116–117.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Laura Sjoberg and Caron Gentry, Mothers, Monsters, Whores: Women’s Violence in Global Politics (London: Zed Books, 2007);

    Google Scholar 

  25. Carolyn Moser and Fiona Clark, eds, Victims, Perpetrators, or Actors? Gender, Armed Conflict, and Political Violence (New York: Zed Books, 2001).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Elshtain, Just War Theory; Jean Bethke Elshtain, Women and War (New York: New York University Press, 1987). Elshtain understands that cultural images of male and female are rooted (at least in part) in just war discourse.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Sara Ruddick, Maternal Thinking: Towards a Politics of Peace (New York: Houghton-Miffin, 1989);

    Google Scholar 

  28. Carol Cohn and Sara Ruddick, “A Feminist Ethical Perspective on Weapons of Mass Destruction,” in S. Lee and S. Hashmi, eds, Ethics and Weapons of Mass Destruction (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002), 405–435.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Nancy Huston, “Tales of War and Tears of Women,” Women’s Studies International Forum 5 (3/4) (1982): 271–282;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. and J. Ann Tickner, Gender in International Relations: Feminist Perspectives on Achieving Global Security (New York: Columbia University Press, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  31. The conceptual conflation here is intentional, representing the same in the policy and academic worlds. As Cynthia Enloe observes, many belligerents do not make a distinction between “womenandchildren” as civilians. See Cynthia Enloe, The Morning After: Sexual Politics at the End of the Cold War (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Jill Steans, Gender and International Relations: An Introduction (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1998), 81.

    Google Scholar 

  33. There are those who have an alternative understanding of this relationship. See R. Charli Carpenter, Innocent Women and Children: Gender, Norms, and the Protection of Civilians (London: Ashgate, 2006);

    Google Scholar 

  34. and R. Charli Carpenter, “Women, Children, and Other Vulnerable Groups: Gender, Strategic Frames, and the Protection of Civilians as a Transnational Issue,” International Studies Quarterly 49 (2) (2005): 295–335. While, in previous work, I have addressed these differences in depth (Sjoberg, “The Gendered Realities of the Immunity Principle”), it is important to note two key points here: first, that work that considers gender subordination rather than just gender as a variable has not only different epistemological and methodological approaches but also different (and I argue richer and more accurate) empirical results; and that violence against women and men must be understood in a larger context of gender symbolism in global politics.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Tickner, Gender in International Relations; J. Ann Tickner, Gendering World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 2001);

    Google Scholar 

  36. Joshua S. Goldstein, War and Gender: How Gender Shapes the War System and Vice Versa (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001).

    Google Scholar 

  37. V. Spike Peterson, “Transgressing Boundaries: Theories of Knowledge, Gender, and International Relations,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 21 (2) (1992): 197.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Nira Yuval-Davis, Gender and Nation (London and Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 1997), 145; Peach, “An Alternative to Pacifism.”

    Google Scholar 

  39. Sjoberg, Gender, Justice, and the Wars in Iraq, citing V. Spike Peterson, “Sexing Political Identities/Nationalism as Heterosexism,” International Feminist Journal of Politics 1 (1) (1999): 34–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Lucian Ashworth and Larry Swatuck, “Masculinity and the Fear of Emasculation in International Relations Theory,” in Marysia Zalewski and Jane Parpart, eds, The “Man” Question in International Relations, (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1998), 86; Elshtain, Just War Theory, 263.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Tickner, Gender in International Relations; Tickner, Gendering World Politics; Sarah Brown, “Feminism, International Theory, and International Relations of Gender Inequality,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 17 (3) (1988): 461–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Christine Sylvester, “Feminists and Realists on Autonomy and Obligation in International Relations,” in V. Spike Peterson, ed., Gendered States (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Press, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  43. Mary E. Hawkesworth, “Knowers, Knowing, Known: Feminist Theory and Claims of Truth,” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 14 (3) (1989): 533–557. Many feminists see the patriarchal state, the war system, the rational man, and international anarchy as constructs of imperial hermeneutics which police meaning in global politics; meaning, in turn, controls the content of international relations stories; which, in turn, limits policy choices.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Nancy Hirschmann, “Freedom, Recognition, and Obligation: A Feminist Approach to Political Theory,” American Political Science Review 83 (4) (1989): 1227–1244. For example, women who become pregnant as a result of rape have assumed responsibility involuntarily. Even though they have not “volunteered,” they now have a responsibility to decide whether to continue the pregnancy, and the attendant responsibilities either to do the work associated with the pregnancy or to terminate it. Each requires action on the part of a woman; the example demonstrates that the supposed voluntariness of social contract — born responsibility is gendered.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Karen Jones, “Gender and Rationality,” in Alfred R. Mele and Piers Rawling, eds, Oxford Handbook on Rationality (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2004), 301–321.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Margaret Atherton, “Cartesian Reason and Gendered Reason,” in Louise M. Antony and Charlotte Witt, eds, A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1993), 19;

    Google Scholar 

  47. Sara Ruddick, “Pacifying the Forces: Drafting Women in the Interest of Peace,” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 8 (3) (1983): 474.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Genevieve Lloyd, “Maleness, Metaphor, and the ‘Crisis’ of Reason,” in Louise M. Antony and Charlotte Witt, eds, A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1993), 77.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Sally Haslanger, “On Being Objective and Objectified,” Antony and Witt, eds, A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1993), 85.

    Google Scholar 

  50. W.B. Slocombe, “Force, Pre-emption, and Legitimacy,” Survival 45 (1) (2003): 117–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Jean Bethke Elshtain, “The Problem with Peace,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 17 (3) (1988): 441–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Hilary Charlesworth, Christine Chinkin, and Shelley Wright, “Feminist Approaches to International Law,” American Journal of International Law 85 (4) (1991): 626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Laura Sjoberg, “Security Studies: Feminist Contributions,” Security Studies 18 (2) (2009): 183–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Cynthia Enloe, Maneuvers: The International Politics of Militarizing Women’s Lives (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  55. Charlotte Hooper, Manly States: Masculinities, International Relations, and Gender Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 2001), 31.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Christine Sylvester, Feminist International Relations: An Unfinished Journey (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2002).

    Google Scholar 

  57. Christine Sylvester, Feminist Theory and International Relations in a Post-modern Era (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 96;

    Google Scholar 

  58. Jill M. Bystudzienski, ed., Women Transforming Politics: Worldwide Strategies for Empowerment (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1992);

    Google Scholar 

  59. Sandra Harding, Is Science Multicultural.? (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  60. Vivienne Jabri, “Explorations of Difference in Normative International Relations,” in Vivienne Jabri and Eleanor O’Gorman, eds., Women, Culture, and International Relations, (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1999), 39–60.

    Google Scholar 

  61. June Lennie, “Deconstructing Gendered Power Relations in Participatory Planning: Towards an Empowering Feminist Framework of Participation and Action,” Women’s Studies International Forum 22 no. 1 (1999): 107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Fiona Robinson, Globalizing Care: Ethics, Feminist Theory, and International Relations (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1999), 47.

    Google Scholar 

  63. See for example Crawford, “Just War Theory and the U.S. Counterterror War”; Robert Imre, T. Brian Mooney, and Benjamin Clarke, Responding to Terrorism: Philosophical and Legal Perspectives (Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, 2007);

    Google Scholar 

  64. Jean Elshtain, Just War against Terror: The Burden of American Power in a Violent World (New York: Basic Books, 2004).

    Google Scholar 

  65. J. Ann Tickner, “Hans Morgenthau’s Principles of Political Realism: A Feminist Reformulation,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 17 no. 3 (1988): 429–440;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  66. and Susan B. Boyd, ed., Challenging the Public — Private Divide (Toronto, ON: University of Toronto Press, 1997).

    Google Scholar 

  67. Edward S. Hermann and Noam Chomsky, Manufacturing Consent: The Political Economy of Mass Media (New York: Pantheon Books, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  68. See Department of Defense Dictionary of Military Terms, 2008, available at http://www.dtic.mil/doctrine/jel/doddict/data/t/05488.html (accessed 1 July 2008); Stanley D. Brunn, 11 September and Its Aftermath: The Geopolitics of Terror (London: Routledge, 2004).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  69. Iris Marion Young, “The Logic of Masculinist Protection and Reflections on the Current Security State,” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 29 no. 1 (2003): 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  70. Mira Sucharov, “Anthologizing the Peace Process,” in Laura Eisenberg, Neil Caplan, Naomi Sokoloff, and Mohammed Abu-Namir, eds., Traditions and Transitions in Israel Studies: Books on Israel, Volume 6 (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2003), 2.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Amy Allen, “Rethinking Power,” Hypatia 13 no. 1 (1998): 21–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  72. Hannah Arendt, On Violence (New York: Harvest Books, 1970); Sjoberg, Gender, Justice, and the Wars in Iraq, 69; Lennie, “Deconstructing Gendered Power Relations in Participatory Planning,” 104.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Robin May Schott, “Gender and ‘Postmodern War’,” Hypatia 11 no. 4 (1996): 19–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  74. Hooper, Manly States, 31; R. W. Connell, Masculinities (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  75. See Chandra Talpade Mohanty, Feminism without Borders: Decolonizing Theory, Practicing Solidarity (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2003).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  76. Gayatri Spivak, “Can the Subaltern Speak?,” in Cary Nelson and Larry Grossberg, eds, Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture (Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 1988), 271–313.

    Google Scholar 

  77. James Turner Johnson, Can Modern War Be Just? (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1984), 28–29.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Sigal Ben-Porath, “Care Ethics and Dependence-Rethinking Jus Post Bellum,” Hypatia 23 (2) (2008): 61–71.

    Google Scholar 

  79. George W. Bush, “The State of the Union Address,” Los Angeles Times, 29 January 2003.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2009 Eric A. Heinze and Brent J. Steele

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sjoberg, L. (2009). Gender, Just War, and Non-state Actors. In: Heinze, E.A., Steele, B.J. (eds) Ethics, Authority, and War. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230101791_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics