Skip to main content

Conclusion: Philosophy, Politics and the Unity of Theory and Practice

  • Chapter
Rethinking R. G. Collingwood
  • 52 Accesses

Abstract

Collingwood’s first major work Speculum Mentis privileges philosophy in taking it to be the pre-eminent conscious activity. Philosophy conceives the world to be coeval with the activity of consciousness. The process of becoming aware of the world corrects the perspectives of subordinate modes of consciousness such as science, art, history and religion, which enact but misperceive the reciprocity of world and consciousness. Philosophy’s reflexive celebration of its apprehension of the role of consciousness raises a number of questions over its interpretation of experience and its evaluation of forms of consciousness. The temptation to dismiss Speculum Mentis as a piece of youthful and exuberant idealism that rejects the objectivity of the world should be resisted. Collingwood’s reluctance to identify himself as an idealist derives from his appreciation of how its label is liable to misrepresentation as a form of world-denying subjectivism. He is at pains to distance himself from such a categorization throughout his career. In Speculum Mentis Collingwood subscribes to an objective idealism that assumes the world to be independent and objective, and yet to be correlated to the succession of ways by which it is apprehended. If Speculum Mentis does not succumb to subjectivism, its deprecation of non-philosophical forms of experience reduces the complexity of experience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. G. W. F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind (trans. Sir James Baillie) (London and New York: George, Allen and Unwin and Humanities Press, p. 81. Hegel: Werke Theorie Werkausgabe (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1970), (eds E. Moldenhauer and K. Michels), Vol. 3 Die Phaenomenologie des Geistes, p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  2. R. G. Collingwood, An Autobiography (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1939), p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  3. R. G. Collingwood, ‘Notes on Historiography’ in R. G. Collingwood, The Principles of History and other writings in philosophy of history (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), p. 238.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See R. G. Collingwood, An Autobiography, p. 66, where Collingwood refers to the purely historical character of metaphysics and R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics (Revised Edition: edited with an Introduction by R. Martin) (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), p. 58. Collingwood refers to metaphysics as an historical science.

    Google Scholar 

  5. W. H. Dray, History as Re-Enactment — R. G. Collingwood’s Idea of History (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  6. L. Rubinoff, Collingwood and the Reform of Metaphysics (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1970), p. 245.

    Google Scholar 

  7. G. D’Oro, Collingwood and the Metaphysics of Experience (London and New York: Routledge, 2002), p. 140.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  8. J. Connelly, Metaphysics, Method and Politics — The Political Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood (Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2003), p. 153.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Philosophical Method (Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 1995), pp. 176–198. See also ‘The Nature of Metaphysical Study’, Collingwood Manuscripts, Bodleian Library, Dep. 18, and ‘Libellus de Geratione’, Collingwood Manuscripts, Bodleain Library, Dep. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  10. R. G. Collingwood, The Idea of Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1940).

    Google Scholar 

  11. See R. G. Collingwood, ‘Notes towards a Metaphysic’, Collingwood Manuscripts, Bodleain Library, Dep. 18. For an explanation of how rational patterns in nature are implicit and await human perception and cognition for their express appreciation. For Collingwood’s account of civilization, which includes reference to mankind’s interaction with nature, see R. G. Collingwood, The New Leviathan (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 280–292.

    Google Scholar 

  12. R. G. Collingwood, ‘Jane Austen’, Collingwood Manuscripts, Bodleian Library, Dep. 17/3; R. G. Collingwood, ‘A Footnote to Future History’ Collingwood Manuscripts, Bodleian Library, Dep. 12/1; R. G. Collingwood, Ruskin’s Philosophy: an address delivered at the Ruskin Centenary (Kendal: Titus Wilson, 1919), pp. 15–22. In these writings, where Hegel is not the principal subject, reference is made to the significance of Hegel’s combination of philosophy and history.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Hegel’s lecture series on the philosophy of right tend to be less quietistic, prompting some commentators to suggest that Hegel’s more conservative standpoint in The Philosophy of Right does not represent his fundamental beliefs. In fact, the lecture series do not alter fundamentally the perspective of The Philosophy of Right. See G. W. F. Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosopie (ed. K. H. Ilting) (Stuttgart: Froman Verlag, 1974). Ilting in the Introduction urges that the lectures cast a new light upon Hegel, indicating the strategic considerations behind his overt conservatism. For a more extended discussion of the matter,

    Google Scholar 

  14. see G. K. Browning, Hegel and the History of Political Philosophy (London and New York: Macmillan, 1999), Introduction.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. R. G. Collingwood, The Idea of Nature, pp. 1–2; K. Marx, Theses on Feuerbach in D. McLellan, Karl Marx: Selected Writings (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  16. G. Graham, The Shape of the Past — A Philosophical Approach to History (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), pp. 1–45.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  17. For a contemporary discussion of nation states in an era of globalization see, D. Held, A. McGrew, D. Goldblatt and J. Perraton, Global Transformations (Cambridge and Oxford: Polity Press, 1999), pp. 32–85.

    Google Scholar 

  18. M. Walzer, Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  19. See J. Rawls, Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy (Cambridge Massachussets and London: Harvard University Press, 2000), pp. 329–373,

    Google Scholar 

  20. and A. MacIntyre, After Virtue (London: Duckworth, 1981), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  21. For a more detailed consideration of the background of Lyotard’s thought, see G. K. Browning, Lyotard and the End of Grand Narratives (Cardiff: University of Wales Press, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  22. See J-F. Lyotard, Peregrinations: Law, Form and Event (New York: Columbia University Press, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  23. J-F. Lyotard, Phenomenology (trans. B. Bleakley) (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  24. See J-F. Lyotard, Political Writings (trans. B. Readings and K. Geiman) (London: UCL Press, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  25. See his writings on the events of May 1968 in J-F Lyotard, Political Writings, (London: UCL Press, 1993), pp. 33–85.

    Google Scholar 

  26. J-F. Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowedge (trans. G. Bennington and B. Massumi) (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  27. J-F. Lyotard, The Differend (trans. G. Van Den Abbeele) (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1988), p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  28. J-F. Lyotard, The Inhuman: Reflections on Time (trans. G. Bennington and R. Bowlby) (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Ibid. pp. 325–336; and see also J-F. Lyotard, Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime trans. E. Rottenberg (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  30. See P. Zagorin, ‘Historiography and Postmodernism: Reconsiderations’ in B. Fay, P. Pomper and R. T. Vann (eds) History and Theory — Contemporary Readings (Oxford: Blackwell, 1998), § 203–204.

    Google Scholar 

  31. J. Rawls, ‘Burton Dreben: A Reminiscence’ in J. Floyd and S. Shieh (eds), Future Pasts: Perspectives on the Place of the Analytic Tradition in Twentieth Century Philosophy (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Rawls’s project of rethinking political theory in the light of its past and the present configuration of social and political practices is evidenced in all of his work, notably in the notion of reflective equilibrium and the revival of the metaphor of the social contract in J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971),

    Google Scholar 

  33. and in his reflections upon the historical emergence of liberalism in J. Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), pp. xxi–xxvii.

    Google Scholar 

  34. R. Bellamy and D. Castiglione, ‘Constitutionalism and Democracy — Political Theory and The American Constitution’, British Journal of Political Science, Vol. 27, 1997, p. 604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. J. Rawls, ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’, in J. Rawls, Collected Papers (ed. S. Freeman) (Cambridge, Mass. and London, England: Harvard University Press, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  36. A. Maclntyre, A Short History of Ethics (London and New York: Macmillan, 1966), p. 255.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  37. Mulhall and Swift classify MacIntyre as a communitarian in their excellent book, S. Muihall and A. Swift, Liberals and Communitarians (Oxford and Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  38. A. MacIntyre, After Virtue (London: Duckworth, 1981), pp. 226–246.

    Google Scholar 

  39. A. MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals (London: Duckworth, 1999), pp. 21–28.

    Google Scholar 

  40. See A. MacIntyre, ‘A Partial Response to My Critics’, in J. Horton and S. Mendus, (eds) After MacIntyre — Critical Perspectives on the Work of Alasdair MacIntyre (Cambridge And Oxford: Polity Press, 1994), p. 302.

    Google Scholar 

  41. R. G. Collingwood, The First Mate’s Log (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1941), p. 150. Collingwood’s critique of utility approaches Marx’s critique of a commodity economy in that he likens the invocation of utility to judge actions to an economy in which commodities only possess exchange value.

    Google Scholar 

  42. On the complex state of sovereignty in the contemporary world see, for instance J. Rosenau, ‘Governance in a Globalizing World’, in D. Held and A. McGrew (eds), The Global Transformations Reader (Oxford and Cambridge, Polity, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  43. See G. K. Browning, Hegel and the History of Political Philosophy (London and New York, Macmillan, 1999).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  44. See, for instance, T. M. Knox, ‘Editor’s Preface’, in R. G. Collingwood, The Idea of History (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2004 Gary K. Browning

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Browning, G.K. (2004). Conclusion: Philosophy, Politics and the Unity of Theory and Practice. In: Rethinking R. G. Collingwood. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230005754_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics