Skip to main content

Attention, Space, Time, and ‘Education’

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Reconstructing 'Education' through Mindful Attention
  • 740 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter begins with William James’s claim ‘for the moment what we attend to is reality’. Based on it we establish attention, space, and time as the fundamentals of mind, which serve as the grounding for the reconstruction of ‘education’. The chapter engages the reader in a series of mindfulness practices, which lead us to develop ‘the matrix of mind’. This matrix grants us with a twofold orientation of attention in space: in here (me) or out there (not-me) and a twofold experience-conception of time: horizontal time axis (past-present-future) or discrete moments of attention (now-now-now). The matrix positions the mind for the reconstruction of ‘education’, defines ‘education’s’ boundaries as a practice of attention, and provides a framework based on which contemporary ‘education’ can be critiqued.

From within this mind-body things do not look quite the same as they do from out there.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 34.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 44.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This is no other than the Buddha’s opening verse of The Dhammapada: ‘All phenomena are preceded by the mind, issue forth from the mind, and consist of the mind.’ (Translated in Wallace [1999, p. 176])

  2. 2.

    I am not claiming that what we know is limited to what we are aware of attending. James indeed claimed that, “[T]he sum total of our impressions never enters our experience” (1984, p. 227). Furthermore, Michael Polanyi (1958) proposed that ‘we know more than we can tell’. My claim is that whatever it is that we do know can only be acknowledged as such, based on the fact that we attended to it.

  3. 3.

    This includes James (1983) and Ellen Langer (1997) about whom I will say much more in Chapter 9. See also Weil (1986) and Lewin (2014).

  4. 4.

    See Merleau-Ponty (1965) for a far more nuanced phenomenology of this domain, that I intentionally avoid here.

  5. 5.

    For the philosophers among you – I am attempting to stick with epistemology and avoid ontology as best I can.

  6. 6.

    This phrasing is inspired by the great Zen teacher Shunryu Suzuki (1999) who spoke in a similar way about the movement of breath in to our bodies, and then out. The conception of a ‘view’ follows neuroscientist Antonio Damasio’s (2005) reference to the ‘view’ of the body in his discussion of Descartes’ erroneous dualism.

  7. 7.

    Cognitive research and neuroscience reassert this. In fact attending in and out involves two different brain networks – the intrinsic and the extrinsic networks respectively (Golland et al. 2007). These two networks are antagonistic (i.e., when one is activated the activity in the other is reduced) (See also, Raichle et al. 2001).

  8. 8.

    There are actually more conceptions. A third one for example, is the timeless that is occasionally featured in this book as well, and has to do with the ‘reflective/philosopher’s I’ (discussed in chapter 9) that works with abstractions such as Platonic forms.

  9. 9.

    If you are wondering ‘who is doing the threading’ or what exactly is the thread that binds these beads, I share your wonder. This book will not offer answers to questions that I cannot answer. It may, however, provide further paths by which to keep questioning and to seek answers.

  10. 10.

    It is important, however, to note that concepts such as ‘flow’ (Csikszentmihalyi 1991) and altered states of mind such as in meditative experiences (Berkovich-Ohana and Glikson 2014) challenge the rather rigid borderlines within this matrix.

References

  • Berkovich-Ohana, A., & Glicksohn, J. (2014). The consciousness state space (CSS)—A unifying model for consciousness and self. Frontiers in Psychology, 5(341), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1991). Flow: The psychology of optimal experience. New York: HarperPerennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (2005). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golland, Y., Bentin, S., Gelbard, H., Benjamini, Y., Heller, R., Nir, Y., Hasson, U., & Malach, R. (2007) Extrinsic and intrinsic systems in the posterior cortex of the human brain revealed during natural sensory stimulation. Cerebral Cortex, 17(4), 766–777.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hans, J. S. (1993). The mysteries of attention. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1983). Talks to teachers on psychology and to students on some of life’s ideals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1984). Psychology, briefer course. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (2007). The principles of psychology. New York, NY: Cosimo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer, E. J. (1997). The power of mindful learning. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley/Addison Wesley Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, D. (2014). Behold: Silence and attention in education. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 48(3), 355–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1965). Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nørretranders, T. (1998). The user illusion: Cutting consciousness down to size. New York: Viking Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1958). Personal knowledge; towards a post-critical philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raichle, M. E., MacLeod, A. M., Snyder, A. Z., Powers, W. J., Gusnard, D. A., & Shulman, G. L. (2001). A default mode of brain function. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 98(2), 676–682.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suzuki, S. (1999). Zen mind, beginner’s mind (1st rev. ed.). New York: Weatherhill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. B. (1999). The Buddhist tradition of Samatha: Methods of refining and examining consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6(2–3), 175–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weil, S. (1986). Simone Weil, an anthology. New York: Weidenfeld & Nicolson. https://www.amazon.com/Simone-Weil-Anthology/dp/0802137296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werner, K. (1996). Effortless mastery: Liberating the master musician within. Albany, NY: Jamey Aebersold Jazz, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ergas, O. (2017). Attention, Space, Time, and ‘Education’. In: Reconstructing 'Education' through Mindful Attention. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-58782-4_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-58782-4_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, London

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-137-58781-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-137-58782-4

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics