Skip to main content

Making the Self, I: Bodily Self-Consciousness

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover The Self and its Defenses

Abstract

The authors argue that there is not a pre-reflective self-consciousness that accompanies every conscious state from birth. This is an empirically void construction, still reminiscent of the Kantian transcendentalism. The outcome of this discussion is that the most minimal form of self-consciousness is bodily self-consciousness, the capacity to construct an analogical and imagistic representation of one’s own body as an entire object, simultaneously taking this representation as a subject, that is, as an active source of the representation of itself. This is coherent with a view of the self in which a distinction (reminiscent of James) must be drawn between the I and the Me, that is, the self as the interminable objectivation process and the self as the multidimensional representation continuously updated by this process.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 63.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Thus, Freud follows Hume’s lesson when he sets up a contrast between the composite, non-monadical character of the mind and its unitary phenomenology. See above, Sect. 2.2.

  2. 2.

    We are painfully aware that Hume’s (and Kant’s) scholarship is endless, and probably every single sentence written by these philosophers is open to contentious interpretation. In what follows we select certain interpretations and offer readings of them that are patently driven by the purpose of paving the way for a more fine-grained analysis of the self based on contemporary empirical research.

  3. 3.

    For a more detailed analysis, see Fogelin (2009, Chap. 6).

  4. 4.

    According to Strawson (1959), descriptive metaphysics aims to describe the most general features of our conceptual scheme; revisionary metaphysics, in contrast, attempts to revise our ordinary way of thinking and our ordinary conceptual scheme.

  5. 5.

    Metzinger in his book Being No One writes: ‘…no such things as selves exist in the world. Nobody ever was or had a self’ (2003, p. 1). Here again the idea is that there is no explanatory role played by the notion of self. For Metzinger even to speak of the self as an illusion may be too much: ‘…there is no one whose illusion the conscious self could be, no one who is confusing herself with anything’ (p. 634). In this sense, he appears even more radical than Dennett.

  6. 6.

    Before starting our analysis a disclaimer is due. The Kantian themes that we are introducing (such as the notion of the ‘I think’, the necessary unity of apperception, the formal nature of the self) have been the object of endless scholarly disputes. Our ambition here, however, is not philological accuracy. Rather we are mainly interested in providing a link between the authoritative tradition of analytical Kantianism inaugurated by Peter Strawson (already mentioned in the previous pages) and contemporary reflections about the self. For a recent discussion of ‘the project of advancing our understanding of the cognitive subject through examining Kant’s theory of cognition’ inaugurated by P. Strawson, see Kitcher (2011).

  7. 7.

    As we shall see in Sect. 4.1.1, according to Locke, the concept of person is not an essence but rather a psychosocial attribute that is assigned to those subjects who possess a specific set of psychological capacities, which makes it possible the continuity of the self and the reflective appropriation of the subject’s actions.

  8. 8.

    In a similar vein John McDowell writes: ‘We can say that the continuity of “consciousness” is intelligible only as a subjective take on something that has more to it than “consciousness” itself contains: on the career of an objective continuant, with which the subject of a continuous “consciousness” can identify itself’ (1996, p. 101).

  9. 9.

    ‘I shall mean by a non-solipsistic consciousness, the consciousness of a being who has a use for the distinction between himself and his states on the one hand, and something not himself or a state of himself, of which he has experience, on the other’ (Strawson, 1959, p. 69).

  10. 10.

    Self-consciousness could be regarded as a particular form of object consciousness, the consciousness of that particular object which is the self. Yet, several developmental stages are required to attain even the most elementary forms of self-consciousness.

  11. 11.

    See below, Sect. 3.3. There we will see that there are different types, or degrees, of self-consciousness. Of course, non-human animals and babies do not possess a narrative self.

  12. 12.

    As Kriegel puts it, ‘…we may ask, Is for-me-ness one more phenomenal item, or merely a non-phenomenal precondition for phenomenality? That is, is there a phenomenology of self-awareness? A deflationist might hold that this for-me-ness is but a dispositional or functional property of conscious states, for example, their global availability to executive function modules; or that it is simply an artifact of the fact that conscious experiences must be someone’s experiences’ (2007, p. 120).

  13. 13.

    See Sect. 3.1.3 above. To be sure, Zahavi distances himself from an anti-naturalist interpretation of phenomenology. He points out, for instance, that ‘[to] naturalize phenomenology might simply be a question of letting phenomenology engage in a fruitful exchange and collaboration with empirical science’ (2009, p. 8). However, it remains to be clarified how naturalized phenomenology can provide evidence for the phenomenally salient sense of mineness: that is our problem.

  14. 14.

    For example, although there is no direct evidence for the activation of mirror neurons in neonates, Gallagher proposes the following hypothesis: ‘…when the neonate sees another person perform a specific motor act, for instance a tongue protrusion, the visual stimulus initiates the firing of the same mirror neurons that are involved in the infant’s own performance of that motor act’ (Gallagher, 2005, p. 77).

  15. 15.

    As Lyyra puts it, ‘Originally, only world is given to the subject’ (2009, p. 76). This is the author’s formulation of what Fonagy, Gergely, Jurist, and Target (2002) call ‘psychic equivalence’.

  16. 16.

    At most we are disposed to concede to Bermúdez that there might be some forms of pre-reflective self-consciousness (at the age of about 18 months), but merely in the sense that it is hard to say whether the representation of one’s own body as one’s own is definitely conceptual. On the nonconceptual versus conceptual character of self-consciousness, see Musholt (2013).

  17. 17.

    To quote Dretske (1995, pp. 100–101), one of the most prominent advocates of first-order representational theories of consciousness.

  18. 18.

    We have here a much thicker intuition than Zahavi’s. It includes, in addition to the primary ownership of the self, a sense of agency: in establishing any sort of active relationship with the world, the individual feels that she is moving from a center in her inner space. In this case the presence is not in the background; rather, it is a starting point, a base upon which the individual proudly sets her foot when she thinks she can say ‘I’.

References

  • Allen, C., & Trestman, M. (2015). Animal consciousness. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/consciousness-animal/

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (1995). Transcendental arguments and psychology. Metaphilosophy, 26, 379–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (1998). The paradox of self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2001). Nonconceptual self-consciousness and cognitive science. Synthese, 129(1), 129–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2007). Self-consciousness. In M. Velmans & S. Schneider (Eds.), The blackwell companion to consciousness (pp. 456–467). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2009). Self: Body awareness and self-awareness. In W. P. Banks (Ed.), Encyclopedia of consciousness (Vol. 2, pp. 289–300). Oxford: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2011). Bodily awareness and self-consciousness. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 157–179). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, P. (2014). Body and self: An entangled narrative. Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brownell, C. A., Svetlova, M., & Nichols, S. R. (2012). Emergence and early development of the body image. In C. Brownell & V. Slaughter (Eds.), Early development of body representation (pp. 37–58). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (1997). Self and world. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Courage, M. L., Edison, S. C., & Howe, M. L. (2004). Variability in the early development of visual self-recognition. Infant Behavior and Development, 27, 509–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1999). The feeling of what happens: Body and emotion in the making of consciousness. New York: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (2010). Self comes to mind. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S. (2014). Consciousness and the brain. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., & Changeux, J.-P. (2011). Experimental and theoretical approaches to conscious processing. Neuron, 70, 200–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1992). The self as a center of narrative gravity. In F. Kessel, P. Cole, & D. Johnson (Eds.), Self and consciousness: Multiple perspectives (pp. 103–115). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2005). Sweet dreams. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2014). Artifactual selves: A response to Lynn Rudder Baker. Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-014-9359-x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C., & Akins, K. (2008). Multiple drafts model. Scholarpedia, 3(4), 4321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C., & Kinsbourne, M. (1992). Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15, 183–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Vignemont, F. (2007). Habeas corpus: The sense of ownership of one’s own body. Mind & Language, 22, 427–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farmer, H., & Tsakiris, M. (2012). The bodily social self: A link between phenomenal and narrative selfhood. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(1), 125–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fogelin, R. J. (1985). Hume’s skepticism in the treatise on human nature. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogelin, R. J. (2009). Hume’s skeptical crisis. A textual study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fonagy, P., Gergely, G., Jurist, E., & Target, M. (2002). Affect regulation, mentalization, and the development of the self. London: Other Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frechette, G. (2013). Searching for the self: Early phenomenological accounts of self-consciousness from Lotze to Scheler. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 21(5), 654–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. London: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (Ed.) (2011). The Oxford handbook of the self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, N., & Meltzoff, A. (1996). The earliest sense of self and others: Merleau-Ponty and recent developmental studies. Philosophical Psychology, 9, 211–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The phenomenological mind: An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2015). Phenomenological approaches to self-consciousness. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/self-consciousness-phenomenological/

  • Hume, D. (2000). A treatise of human nature (D. F. Norton & M. J. Norton, Eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. (orig. ed. 1739–1740).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. T. (2006). Saving the baby: Dennett on autobiography, agency, and the self. Philosophical Psychology, 19, 345–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1950). The principles of psychology. New York: Dover. (orig. ed. 1890).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jervis, G. (2011). In G. Corbellini & M. Marraffa (Eds.), Il mito dell’interiorità. Turin: Bollati Boringhieri.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, S. S. (2009). The development of imitation in infancy. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B. Biological Sciences, 364, 2325–2335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (orig. ed. 1781–1787).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kapitan, T. (1999). The ubiquity of self-awareness. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 57, 17–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). Kant’s thinker. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kouider, S., Stahlhut, C., Gelskov, S., Barbosa, L., Dutat, M., de Gardelle, V., Christophe, A., Dehaene, S., & Dehaene-Lambertz, G. (2013). A neural marker of perceptual consciousness in infants. Science, 340, 376–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2007). The phenomenologically manifest. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(1–2), 115–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2008). The sources of intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M. (1994). Myself and me. In S. Parker, R. Mitchell, & M. Boccia (Eds.), Self-awareness in animals and humans: Developmental perspectives (pp. 20–34). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M., & Brooks-Gunn, J. (1979). Social cognition and the acquisition of the self. New York and London: Plenum Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M., & Carmody, D. P. (2008). Self-representation and brain development. Developmental Psychology, 44, 1329–1334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M., & Ramsay, D. (2004). Development of self-recognition, personal pronoun use, and pretend play during the 2nd year. Child Development, 75, 1821–1831.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lichtenberg, J. D. (1989). Psychoanalysis and motivation. Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyyra, P. (2009). Two senses for ‘givenness of consciousness’. Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences, 8, 67–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C. (2008). Introduction. In K. Atkins & C. Mackenzie (Eds.), Practical identity and narrative agency (pp. 1–28). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McAdams, D. P. (1996). Personality, modernity, and the storied self: A contemporary framework for studying persons. Psychological Inquiry, 7, 295–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAdams, D. P. (1997). The case for unity in the (post)modern self: A modest proposal. In R. D. Ashmore & L. Jussim (Eds.), Self and identity. Fundamental issues (pp. 46–78). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McAdams, D. P., & Cox, K. S. (2010). Self and identity across the life span. In R. M. Lerner (Ed.), The handbook of life-span development (Vol. 2, pp. 158–207). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1995). Infants’ understanding of people and things: From body imitation to folk psychology. In J. Bermudez, A. J. Marcel, & N. Eilan (Eds.), The body and the self (pp. 43–69). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2010). Child psychology and pedagogy. The Sorbonne lectures 1949–1952. Evaston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2003). Being no one. The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2011). The no-self alternative. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 279–296). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musholt, K. (2013). Self-consciousness and nonconceptual content. Philosophical Studies, 163, 649–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, M., Dissanayake, C., & Kashima, Y. (2003). A longitudinal investigation of self-other discrimination and the emergence of mirror self-recognition. Infant Behavior and Development, 26, 213–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, S., Mitchell, R., & Boccia, M. (Eds.) (1994). Self-awareness in animals and humans: Developmental perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2014). Kant’s transcendental arguments. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/kant-transcendental/

  • Peterfreund, E. (1978). Some critical comments on psychoanalytic conceptualizations of infancy. The International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 59, 427–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prebble, S. C., Addis, D. R., & Tippett, L. J. (2013). Autobiographical memory and sense of self. Psychological Bulletin, 139, 815–840.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rochat, P. (2012). Primordial sense of an embodied self-unity. In V. Slaughter & C. Brownell (Eds.), Early development of body representations (pp. 3–18). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohlf, M. (2014). Immanuel Kant. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/kant/

  • Schear, J. C. (2009). Experience and self-consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 144, 95–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. (2011). The narrative self. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 394–416). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, S. (2007). Daniel Dennett on the nature of consciousness. In M. Velmans & S. Schneider (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to consciousness (pp. 313–324). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1969). The world as will and representation. New York: Dover. (orig. ed. 1819).

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. London: Methuen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1966). The bounds of sense. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (1977). Hume. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T., & Butler, D. L. (2013). The nature of visual self-recognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(3), 121–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasetta, A. (2015). Persone umane. Rome: Carocci.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2003). Consciousness and persons. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welsh, T. (2006). Do neonates display innate self-awareness? Why neonatal imitation fails to provide sufficient grounds for innate self and other awareness. Philosophical Psychology, 19, 221–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Welsh, T. (2007). Primal experience in Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy and psychology. Radical Psychology, 6(1), http://www.radpsynet.org/journal/vol6-1/index.html

  • Welsh, T. (2013). The child as natural phenomenologist. Primal and primary experience in Merleau-Ponty’s psychology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2007). Self and other: The limits of narrative understanding. In D. D. Hutto (Ed.), Narrative and understanding persons (pp. 179–201). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2012). The time of the self. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 84, 143–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2014). Self and other. Exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2015). Self and other: From pure ego to co-constituted we. Continental Philosophy Review, 48(2), 143–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2016 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Di Francesco, M., Marraffa, M., Paternoster, A. (2016). Making the Self, I: Bodily Self-Consciousness. In: The Self and its Defenses. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-57385-8_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics