Skip to main content

Re-examining Samuelson’s Operationalist Methodology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 681 Accesses

Part of the book series: Remaking Economics: Eminent Post-War Economists ((EPWE))

Abstract

During the heyday of discussion about Milton Friedman’s 1953 methodology paper, Samuelson’s operationalism was often discussed as the primary competitor to Friedman’s position. Although Friedman’s paper continues to be discussed—albeit at a steadily decreasing rate—Samuelson’s account of economic methodology has all but disappeared from the literature. This paper offers a re-examination of Samuelson’s account. Why a re-examination now? There are many reasons, but I will focus on just two. The first is that the historical research on Samuelson has exploded since his death in 2009, primarily because of the extensive archival material he left behind. The second is Samuelson’s revealed preference theory; it is methodologically relevant because Samuelson insisted it was an exemplar of his operationalist approach.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   165.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Box 71, Paul A. Samuelson Papers, Economists’ Papers Archive, David M. Rubenstein Rare Book & Manuscript Library, Duke University (all archival references in this chapter refer to the Economists’ Papers Archive at Duke).

  2. 2.

    This literature includes Archibald (1963), Cohen (1995), Garb (1965), Gordon (1955a, b), Lerner (1965), Machlup (1964, 1966), Massey (1965), Nagel (1963), Samuelson (1955, 1963, 1964, 1965), Simon (1963), and Wong (1973, 2006).

  3. 3.

    I say “most” and not “all” because there were some American pragmatists—John Dewey in particular—who were sympathetic to operationalist ideas but interpreted them differently than most operationalists and did not self-identify with the positivist tradition. See Hands (2004) for a discussion of these issues.

  4. 4.

    See any of the traditional texts on so-called received view philosophy of science (e.g., Hempel 1965; Nagel 1961; Suppe 1977) or for a discussion of these issues with an eye toward economics, see Caldwell (1994: Chapters 2–4) or Hands (2001: Chapter 3).

  5. 5.

    The literature is extensive, but a wide-ranging sample is Bergmann (1954), Chang (2009), Gillies (1972), Green (1992), Hempel (1954), Nagel (1961), and Suppe (1972, 1977).

  6. 6.

    When one discusses operationalism in psychology and to a lesser extent economics, one immediately raises the question of the impact of behaviorism in these social sciences, since operationalism is frequently—sometimes correctly and sometime incorrectly—associated with behaviorism. But the impact of behaviorism and its relationship to operationalism in the social sciences is a very complex topic that has generated a massive literature in the history and philosophy of the social sciences. Given this, I will stay on task and defer the broader question of behaviorism for another time. Here, I will focus exclusively on Samuelson and his operationalist methodology sans behaviorism.

  7. 7.

    Wong (1973: 319) discussed six of Samuelson’s different arguments and raised reasonable concerns about each.

  8. 8.

    In many ways, it is disappointing that Samuelson continued to say the same things about economic methodology in published work throughout his life. It is disappointing because there are a few places in his correspondence where he expressed not only understanding of, but sympathy for, some of the ideas in post-positivist philosophy of science. For example: “the real objection to positivism in philosophy, I suppose, is that when you get down to the nitty-gritty, at the very frontier of what you mean about meaning, it cannot deliver the goods. When I read…Quine on Two Dogmas…I am distressed – because the simple-minded distinctions that my youthful reading of Ayer and other such types made me think can be maintained turn out to be fuzzy and even self-contradictory. And most logical positivists of the 1930s, who have not gone senile have recanted on their faith in their simplicities” (Samuelson to Hahn, 14 January, 1972, Box 36).

  9. 9.

    This human and intentional property of operations was precisely that which attracted pragmatists like John Dewey to operationalism even though they were generally anti-positivist. See Footnote 3.

  10. 10.

    I would suggest that he was a little less successful than Backhouse and Carvajalino seem to argue. Two of the reasons for this are: (i) the sheer fact that the number of pages in Foundations (and Samuelson’s later work) where the analysis is conducted in terms of derivatives and differential equations is significantly larger than the amount conducted in terms of discrete mathematics and (ii) also the fact that many of the linear inequalities are linear because they come from Jacobian or Hessian matrices and were thus also calculus-based. Note that this is not a criticism of the argument that Samuelson was trying to do mathematical economics in a Wilsonian way—it seems clear he was. It simply means that discrete mathematics was extremely difficult in the pre-computer age. Another factor may have been that Samuelson always saw his work as fitting into, and improving on, the grand flow of economic ideas, and doing that, and having it recognized as such, is much easier when the theory is couched in the same mathematical formalism.

  11. 11.

    Since this chapter is primarily concerned with Samuelson’s methodology and not his economic theory, it is useful to note that RPT was fundamentally a methodological program. Samuelson did not introduce RPT because of some practical problem with ordinal utility theory, for example, to correct for particular empirical refutations or anomalies or to extend the possible range of application of the theory. He was trying to develop a theory that would have the same empirical implications as ordinal utility theory—the exact same Slutsky conditions—but one that would rest on more epistemically palatable foundations. As Daniel Hausman explains: “The raison d’être of revealed-preference theory was philosophical. It was supposed to enable economists to rid economic theory of references to subjective preferences or to make those references respectable” (Hausman 2000: 112).

  12. 12.

    Samuelson says that WARP was “logically equivalent to the reformulation of Hicks and Allen,” but that is not the case in general (although it is true for only two goods), although Samuelson did not know this at the time (and nor did anyone else). It was not until Houthakker’s paper that it became clear that it was SARP, not WARP, that was equivalent to OUT. It was not until, as Samuelson put it: “Mr. Houthakker’s paper arrived in the daily mail” (Samuelson 1950: 370).

  13. 13.

    Samuelson “New Foundations for the Pure Theory of Consumer’s Behavior,” Box 152 (no date, but definitely from the 1930s; it says “Paul A. Samuelson Harvard University”). Backhouse says the paper “is undated but is assumed to be 1937” (Backhouse 2017: 652, fn. 40).

  14. 14.

    My assessment is thus similar to what Hausman calls the “methodological schizophrenia” of economics, whereby “methodological doctrine and practice regularly contradict one another. This schizophrenia is a symptom of the unsound philosophical premises underlying…economic methodology” (Hausman 1992: 152). I would also note that Samuelson’s use of abstract mathematical functions presumed to be “empirically determinable under ideal conditions” was typical of the theoretical economics of his day. It may not seem very “empirical” today, but it was standard practice then. See Hands (2017a) for more details.

  15. 15.

    See Varian (2006) or Vermeulen (2012) for a general discussion of the GARP-based literature and the importance of Afriat’s work in its development. Moscati and Tubaro (2011) discuss some of the early applications of these techniques, while Andreoni et al. (2013), Cherchye et al. (2009), and Crawford and De Rock (2014) provide accessible discussions of the empirical revealed preference literature. Various aspects of this literature are discussed in Hands (2013, 2017a, b).

References

  • Afriat S.N. (1967) “The Construction of Utility Functions from Expenditure Data,” International Economic Review, 8: 67–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni J., B.J. Gillen and W.T. Harbaugh (2013) “The Power of Revealed Preference Tests: Ex-Post Evaluation of Experimental Design,” Working Paper, Department of Economics, University of Oregon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archibald, G.C. (1963) “Problems of Methodology—Discussion,” American Economic Review, 53: 227–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Backhouse, R.E. (2015) “Revisiting Samuelson’s Foundations of Economic Analysis,” Journal of Economic Literature, 53: 326–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Backhouse, R.E. (2017) Founder of Modern Economics: Paul A. Samuelson, Volume I: Becoming Samuelson, 1915–1948. New York, Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann, G. (1954) “Sense and Nonsense in Operationism,” The Scientific Monthly, 79: 210–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blaug, M. (1992) The Methodology of Economics: Or How Economists Explain. Second edition. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. First edition, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boumans, M. and J. Davis (2015) Economic Methodology: Understanding Economics as a Science. Second edition. New York, Palgrave. First edition, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bridgman, P.W. (1927) The Logic of Modern Physics. New York, Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bridgman, P.W. (1954) “Remarks on the Present State of Operationalism,” The Scientific Monthly, 79: 224–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caldwell, B.J. (1994) Beyond Positivism: Economic Methodology in the Twentieth Century. Reissued with new preface. London, George Allen & Unwin. First edition, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carvajalino, J. (2016) Edwin B. Wilson at the Origin of Paul Samuelson’s Mathematical Economics: Essays on the Interwoven History of Economics, Mathematics and Statistics in the US: 1900–1940. PhD dissertation, University of Montreal at Quebec.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carvajalino, J. (2018) “Samuelson’s Operationally Meaningful Theorems: Reflections of E.B. Wilson’s Methodological Attitude,” Journal of Economic Methodology, 25: 143–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2009) “Operationalism,” in E.N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Fall 2009 edition. Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/operationalism/.

  • Cherchye, L., I. Crawford, B. De Rock and F. Vermeulen (2009) “The Revealed Preference Approach to Demand,” in D.J. Slottje (ed.) Quantifying Consumer Preferences. Bingley, UK, Emerald Group Publishing: 247–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (1995) “Samuelson’s Operationalist-Descriptivist Thesis,” Journal of Economic Methodology, 2: 57–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crawford, I. and B. De Rock (2014) “Empirical Revealed Preference,” Annual Review of Economics, 6: 503–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diewert, W.E. (1973) “Afriat and Revealed Preference Theory,” Review of Economic Studies, 40: 419–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1953) “The Methodology of Positive Economics,” in M. Friedman (ed.) Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago, University of Chicago Press: 3–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garb, G. (1965) “Professor Samuelson on Theory and Realism: Comment,” American Economic Review, 55: 1151–1153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D.A. (1972) “Operationalism,” Synthese, 25: 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, D.F. (1955a) “Operational Propositions in Economic Theory,” Journal of Political Economy, 63: 150–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, D.F. (1955b) “Professor Samuelson on Operationalism in Economic Theory,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69: 305–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, C.D. (1992) “Of Immortal Mythological Beasts: Operationism in Psychology,” Theory & Psychology, 2: 291–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D.W. (2001) Reflection without Rules: Economic Methodology and Contemporary Science Theory. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D.W. (2004) “On Operationalisms and Economics,” Journal of Economic Issues, 38: 953–968.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D.W. (2013) “Foundations of Contemporary Revealed Preference Theory,” Erkenntnis, 78: 1081–1108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D.W. (2014) “Paul Samuelson and Revealed Preference Theory,” History of Political Economy, 46: 85–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D.W. (2017a) “The Road to Rationalization: A History of ‘Where the Empirical Lives’ (or has Lived) in Consumer Choice Theory,” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 24: 555–588.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D.W. (2017b) “Revealed Preference, Afriat’s Theorem, and Falsifiability: A Review Essay on Revealed Preference Theory by C.P. Chambers and F. Echenique,” Oeconomia, 7: 409–438.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D.M. (1992) The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D.M. (2000) “Revealed Preference, Belief, and Game Theory,” Economics and Philosophy, 16: 99–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. (1954) “A Logical Appraisal of Operationism,” The Scientific Monthly, 79: 215–220. Reprinted as Chapter 5 of C.G. Hempel (1965) Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York, The Free Press: 123–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. (1965) Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York, The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hicks, J.R. and R.G.D. Allen (1934) “A Reconsideration of the Theory of Value, Parts I and II,” Economica, New Series, 1: 52–76, 196–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houthakker, H.S. (1950) “Revealed Preference and the Utility Function,” Economica, New Series, 17: 159–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lerner, A.P. (1965) “Professor Samuelson on Theory and Realism: Comment,” American Economic Review, 55: 1153–1155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machlup, F. (1964) “Professor Samuelson on Theory and Realism,” American Economic Review, 54: 733–735.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machlup, F. (1966) “Operationalism and Pure Theory in Economics,” in S.R. Krupp (ed.) The Structure of Economic Science: Essays on Methodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall: 53–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massey, G.J. (1965) “Professor Samuelson on Theory and Realism: Comment,” American Economic Review, 55: 1155–1164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Medema, S.G. and A.M.C. Waterman (eds.) (2015) Paul Samuelson on the History of Economic Analysis. New York, Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moscati, I. (2007) “Early Experiments in Consumer Demand Theory: 1930–1970,” History of Political Economy, 39: 359-401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moscati, I. and P. Tubaro (2011) “Becker Random Behavior and the As-If Defense of Rational Choice Theory in Demand Analysis,” Journal of Economic Methodology, 18: 107–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961) The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. New York, Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1963) “Assumptions in Economic Theory,” American Economic Review, 53: 211–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, K.A and K.D. Hoover (1995) “After the Revolution: Paul Samuelson and the Textbook Keynesian Model,” in A.F. Cottrell and M.S. Lawlor (eds.) New Perspectives on Keynes. Annual supplement to History of Political Economy, 27. Durham, Duke University Press: 183–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollak, R.A. (1990) “Distinguished Fellow: Houthakker’s Contributions to Economics,” Journal of Economic Perspectives, 4: 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1938a) “The Empirical Implications of Utility Analysis,” Econometrica, 6: 344–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1938b) “A Note on the Pure Theory of Consumer’s Behaviour,” Economica, New Series, 5: 61–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1940) Foundations of Analytical Economics: The Observational Significance of Economic Theory PhD dissertation, Harvard University. Box 91 of Samuelson Papers, Duke University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1947) Foundations of Economic Analysis. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1948a) Economics: An Introductory Analysis. New York, McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1948b) “Consumption Theory in Terms of Revealed Preference,” Economica, New Series, 15: 243–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1950) “The Problem of Integrability in Utility Theory,” Economica, New Series, 17: 355–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1955) “Professor Samuelson on Operationalism in Economic Theory: Comment,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69: 310–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1963) “Problems of Methodology—Discussion,” American Economic Review, 53: 231–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1964) “Theory and Realism: A Reply,” American Economic Review, 54: 736–739.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1965) “Professor Samuelson on Theory and Realism: Reply,” American Economic Review, 55: 1164–1172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1972) “Maximum Principles in Analytical Economics,” American Economic Review, 62: 249–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1983) Foundations of Economic Analysis. Enlarged edition. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1991) “My Life Philosophy: Policy Credos and Working Ways,” in M. Szenberg (ed.) Eminent Economists: Their Life Philosophies. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press: 236–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A. (1998) “How Foundations Came to Be,” Journal of Economic Literature, 36: 1375–1386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.A. (1963) “Problems of Methodology—Discussion,” American Economic Review, 53: 229–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (1972) “Theories, Their Formulations, and the Operational Imperative,” Synthese, 25: 129–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (ed.) (1977) The Structure of Scientific Theories. Second edition. Urbana, University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (1979) “Theory Structure,” in P. Asquith and H. Kyburg (eds.) Current Research in Philosophy of Science. East Lansing, MI, Philosophy of Science Association: 317–338.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varian, H.R. (1982) “The Nonparametric Approach to Demand Analysis,” Econometrica, 50: 945–973.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varian, H.R. (2006) “Revealed Preference,” in M. Szenberg, L. Ramrattan and A.A. Gottesman (eds.) Samuelsonian Economics and the Twenty-First Century. Oxford, Oxford University Press: 99–115.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vermeulen, F. (2012) “Foundations of Revealed Preference: Introduction,” Economic Journal, 122: 287–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wong, S. (1973) “The ‘F-Twist’ and the Methodology of Paul Samuelson,” American Economic Review, 63: 312–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wong, S. (2006) The Foundations of Paul Samuelson’s Revealed Preference Theory: A Study by the Method of Rational Reconstruction. Revised edition. London, Routledge. Originally published in 1978.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to D. Wade Hands .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Wade Hands, D. (2019). Re-examining Samuelson’s Operationalist Methodology. In: Cord, R., Anderson, R., Barnett, W. (eds) Paul Samuelson. Remaking Economics: Eminent Post-War Economists. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-56812-0_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-56812-0_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, London

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-137-56811-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-137-56812-0

  • eBook Packages: Economics and FinanceEconomics and Finance (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics