Skip to main content

Critique as the Epistemic Framework of the Critical Social Sciences

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Political Philosophy and Public Purpose ((POPHPUPU))

Abstract

This chapter explores the different features of the critical method as an epistemological and methodological underpinning for the critical social sciences and for critical theory more generally, and furthermore calls into question the prevailing methodological assumptions and theses that underpin the mainstream contemporary social sciences. It argues that critique as a method of knowledge production breaks with the most basic and deeply entrenched methodological assumptions and logics of the mainstream social sciences. The author explores the basic pillars of the critical method: the nature of reality as dynamic and processual rather than discrete and static, the nature of the unification of “factual” knowledge claims and “normative” or “evaluative” knowledge claims, and the relation between essence and appearance in the comprehension of social facts and social reality more generally. The chapter concludes with a consideration of the nature of critical judgment as an essential aim of critical theory or critical social sciences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Habermas maintains that this split between the empirical and practical dimensions of philosophy occurred much earlier: “Prior to positivism, critical knowledge referred to a scientific orientation in action … However, after the empirical sciences of the new type, so successful since the time of Galileo, had attained a consciousness of themselves in positivism, and after analytic philosophy, inspired by the Vienna circle as well as by Peirce and Dewey, had explicated this self-understanding in terms of the philosophy of science, especially in the work of Carnap, Popper, and Morris, the two cognitive functions were distinctly separated – and both deprived of their power of orientation for action” (Habermas 1973: 263). Although Habermas is correct to point to this as a decisive feature of the development of modern forms of science and its separation from practical rationality, it is clear that thinkers such as Hegel and Marx were attempting to formulate a modern form of philosophical science that would once again unite the cognitive and practical features of a fuller form of human rationality.

  2. 2.

    Weber notes: “Normative standards of value can and must be the objects of dispute in a discussion of a problem of social policy because the problem lies in the domain of general cultural values” (Weber 1963: 362). Cf. the discussion by Ringer (1997: 122ff.).

  3. 3.

    Marx’s theory of scientific knowledge makes a similar claim in that the object itself dictates the kinds of reasoning needed for its comprehension, hence the materialist understanding of matter preceding consciousness. As Patrick Murray has explained: “This entails necessity in that the relation between the ‘facts’ and the logic that is to draw them together into the shape of a science sheds its arbitrariness. The object under study determines the science now in second intension; it determines the logic of the ‘facts.’ Marx’s critique of empiricism is immanent in calling empiricism to submit the question of the relation of ‘facts’ and their logical reconstruction itself to empirical scrutiny. This critical approach to concepts and their logical interconnections is one of the features that sets Marx’s theory of scientific knowledge apart from positivist understandings of science” (Murray 1988: 41). Also see McCarthy (1988: 135ff.).

  4. 4.

    Westphal correctly notes on this point: “Because the essential interrelation between ‘appearance’ and ‘reality’ would determine the characteristics of each of them, a thorough investigation of appearances would lead one to comprehend ‘reality’ as well” (Westphal 1989: 145).

  5. 5.

    Norman Geras says on this point that “the content explains the form, and the essence the appearances. But this must not be regarded as a journey from illusion to reality. It is rather a process of elucidating one reality by disclosing its foundation and determination by another” (Geras 1971: 77).

  6. 6.

    Howard Williams correctly suggests, for Marx: “Empirical reality exists just as much as does scientific reality. The one can be observed by the senses and the other can be discovered by the intellect. Marx subscribes to two distinct concepts of appearance, therefore, because appearance possesses these two aspects” (Williams 1989: 144).

  7. 7.

    In the Preface to the Phänomenologie, Hegel writes: “Among the many consequences that follow from what has been said, it is important to emphasize this: that knowledge is only real and is only fully put forth in the form of science, in the form of a system” (Hegel 1970b: 27). Also see the discussion by Westphal (1989: 140ff.).

  8. 8.

    This was also the position worked out by Lukács (1971) when he argued that part of the effect of reification was the impression of economic logics onto the categories of social science and social philosophy itself constituting what he calls “antinomies of bourgeois thought.”

  9. 9.

    Adorno therefore writes that, when studying the psychological structure of the individual, that the “[p]ersonality is not … to be hypostatized as an ultimate determinant. Far from being something which is given in the beginning, which remains fixed and acts upon the surrounding world, personality evolves under the impact of the social environment and can never be isolated from the social totality within which is occurs” (Adorno et al. 1950: 5). Cf. Fromm (1971).

References

  • Adorno, T.W. 1982. Subject and object. In The essential Frankfurt School reader, ed. Andrew Arato, and Eike Gebhardt. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Hegel: Three studies. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Scientific experiences of a European scholar in America. In Critical models. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, T.W., et al. 1950. The authoritarian personality. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, Werner. 1970. Idealistische und Materialistische Dialektik. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, James. 1999. Theories, practices, and pluralism: A pragmatic interpretation of critical social science. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 29(4): 459–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Michael E. 2014. The concept of the social in uniting the humanities and social sciences. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caterino, Brian. 2016. The practical import of political inquiry. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dahms, Harry. 2008. How social science is impossible without critical theory: The immersion of mainstream approaches in time and space. Current Perspectives in Social Theory 26: 3–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Della Volpe, Galvano. 1980. Logic as a positive science. London: New Left Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fromm, Erich. 1971. The crisis of psychoanalysis. New York: Henry Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geras, Norman. 1971. Essence and appearance: aspects of fetishism in Marx’s Capital. New Left Review 65: 31–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1973. Theory and practice. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. 1970a. Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften I: Logik. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1970b. Phänomenologie des Geistes. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, Max. 1972. Traditional and critical theory. In Critical theory. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1982. On the problem of truth. In The essential Frankfurt School reader, ed. Andrew Arato, and Eike Gebhardt. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, Winfred. 1976. Zur Dialektik von Substanz und Subjekt bei Hegel und Marx. Frankfurt: Haag und Herchen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreines, James. 2015. Reason in the world: Hegel’s metaphysics and its philosophical appeal. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lazarsfeld, Paul. 1941. Remarks on administrative and critical communications research. Studies in Philosophy and Social Science 9: 2–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lukács, Georg. 1971. History and class consciousness: Studies in Marxist dialectics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl. 1973. Grundrisse. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, George. 1988. Marx’s critique of science and positivism: The methodological foundations of political economy. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, Patrick. 1988. Marx’s theory of scientific knowledge. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ringer, Fritz. 1997. Max Weber’s methodology: The unification of the cultural and social sciences. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, Stanley. 2014. The idea of Hegel’s Science of logic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, Nathan. 2008. On mechanism in Hegel’s social and political philosophy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Hegel’s logical critique of capitalism: The paradox of dependence and the model of reciprocal mediation. In Hegel and capitalism, ed. Andrew Buchwalter, 163–180. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John. 2010. Making the social world: The structure of human civilization. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Tony. 1993. Dialectical social theory and its critics: From Hegel to analytical Marxism and postmodernism. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strydom, Piet. 2011. Contemporary critical theory and methodology. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Susen, Simon. 2015. The “postmodern turn” in the social sciences. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Michael J. 2014. The base-superstructure hypothesis and the foundations of critical theory. Current Perspectives in Social Theory 32: 161–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Philosophical foundations for a Marxian ethics. In Constructing Marxist ethics: Critique, normativity, praxis, ed. M. Thompson, 235–265. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1963. ‘Objectivity’ in social science and social policy. In Philosophy of the social sciences, ed. Maurice Natanson. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1973. Der Sinn der ‘Wertfreiheit’ der soziologischen und ökonomischen Wissenschaften. In Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westphal, Kenneth. 1989. Hegel’s epistemological realism. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • White, Stephen K. 2004. The very idea of a critical social science: A pragmatic turn. In The Cambridge companion to critical theory, ed. Fred Rush, 310–335. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Howard. 1989. Hegel, Heraclitus and Marx’s dialectic. New York: St. Martin’s.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wrong, Dennis. 1961. The oversocialized conception of man in modern sociology. American Sociological Review 26(2): 183–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Thompson, M.J. (2017). Critique as the Epistemic Framework of the Critical Social Sciences. In: Thompson, M. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Theory. Political Philosophy and Public Purpose. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-55801-5_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics