Skip to main content

Moderate Conceptualism and Spatial Representation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Kantian Nonconceptualism

Abstract

Thomas Land argues that Kant’s theory of spatial representation supports a moderately conceptualist view of his theory of intuition. In making the case for this he focuses on three aspects of he theory of spatial representation: the distinction Kant draws between the original representation of space and the representations of determinate spaces, the doctrine of the productive imagination and the doctrine of the a priori determination of sensibility by the understanding. He explains why these three aspects support a moderately conceptualist view and considers a number of objections.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For two notable exceptions see Onof and Schulting (2015) and Tolley, Chap. 11 in this volume.

  2. 2.

    For instances of such a reading, see Allais (2009, 2015), Golob (2014), Hanna (2005, 2008, 2011b), McLear (2014b, 2015) and Tolley (2013). The position is usually defined in terms of a dependence on the possession of concepts. While this is not incorrect, I believe it is more fruitful to frame the issue in terms of the dependence (or otherwise) on exercises of spontaneity, as the focus on concepts can lead to a distorted picture of the doctrine of sensible synthesis, to be introduced below. See Land (2015b) for discussion. Note that my claims in this chapter are limited to the kinds of intuitions that mature human beings enjoy. Non-human animal intuitions, for instance, do not exhibit the kind of spontaneity-dependence I claim here for mature human intuitions. I discuss this issue in Land (forthcoming).

  3. 3.

    A note on terminology: I take it that the notion of a capacity (power) and its exercise or actualisations is fundamental to Kant’s discussion. Thus, sensibility and understanding are capacities, and the representations Kant attributes to them (intuitions, concepts, etc.) are their actualisations, exercise or acts. Talk of “act” in this connection carries no implication of being active as opposed to passive; a passive (receptive) power can be in act just as much as an active (spontaneous) power.

  4. 4.

    On this definition of nonconceptualism, the view can allow for the possibility of actualisations of sensibility that, as a matter of fact, do involve acts of spontaneity. The point is that this is not necessary for intuition to represent objects in the relevant sense.

  5. 5.

    See e.g. Ginsborg (2008), Griffith (2012), Grüne (2009), Land (2015a), Longuenesse (1998a), McDowell (1998, 2009), Pippin (1982) and Sellars (1967, 1978).

  6. 6.

    It should be noted that this term is not Kant’s. I use it as a generic label for any act of synthesis (among which Kant appears to distinguish different species) that is distinct from synthesis in judgement in the way I explicate below.

  7. 7.

    Note that these labels are used in different ways. See Schulting (2015b) for an alternative usage.

  8. 8.

    Thus, the versions of Ginsborg (2008), Grüne (2009), Longuenesse (1998a) and Sellars (1967, 1978) all differ from my own.

  9. 9.

    It might be thought that being extended in time makes sensible synthesis empirical, since time for Kant is a form of empirical intuition. But this is not Kant’s view; see e.g. B155n.: “Motion, as description of a space, is a pure act of the successive synthesis of the manifold in outer intuition in general through productive imagination” (emphasis added).

  10. 10.

    See A103; B154; B155n.; A145/B184; A163/B203–4; A167–8/B209–10; A170/B211–12.

  11. 11.

    Judging is an act of the intellect, that is, an act of the subject’s “self-activity” or “spontaneity” (B130). It is not a sensible representing. As a consequence, it is not subject to the form of inner sense, time. Nor, therefore, is it extended in time. This is not to deny that we can have sensible representations of our own mental states. For helpful discussion see Geach (1969).

  12. 12.

    This is compatible with holding that the content of some concepts is, or includes, a spatiotemporal manifold.

  13. 13.

    See A99–102; B151–2; B153–4; B160n.; B162n.; A141–2/B180–1; B202–3; A163/B204; A170/B211–12; A723/B751.

  14. 14.

    For detailed discussion see Land (2015a). Thanks to Dennis Schulting for requesting clarification of this point.

  15. 15.

    This point is central to the work of John McDowell (see e.g. McDowell 1998, 2009). See also Engstrom (2006).

  16. 16.

    An analogous point applies to inner intuitions and time.

  17. 17.

    So I shall not engage with strong conceptualism here. I do so in Land (2015b). Note, however, that the discussion below in Sect. 7.4 provides reasons for rejecting strong conceptualism.

  18. 18.

    For discussion of this point, see Longuenesse (1998a:214–27) and Sutherland (2005a).

  19. 19.

    See B154; A162–3/B203–4; A170/B211.

  20. 20.

    For the claim that Kant uses terms like “intuition” in both of these senses, see Sellars (1976:405, 413–16) and Allison (2004:82).

  21. 21.

    See McLear (2014b:771–2, 779–80) and Tolley (2013:123–25).

  22. 22.

    See Allais (2015:171–2) and McLear (2015:88, 93–4).

  23. 23.

    It should be noted that the textual evidence for the terminological claim is ambiguous. Besides passages that seem to suggest it (see, in addition to B162 and B202–3, Prol, 4:304), there are also passages suggesting the opposite (e.g. B422n.; Anth, 7:134n.). What seems clear is that Kant uses “perception” (Wahrnehmung) to refer to what, without begging the question, can be described as the combination of empirical intuition and consciousness (see e.g. ÜE, 8:217). It is less clear what this implies regarding the meaning of “empirical intuition”. Addressing this issue fully would exceed the scope of this chapter. However, following Allison (2004:193) I wish to note that locutions like “making an empirical intuition into a perception” (cf. B162) can equally well be explained by noting that terms like “intuition” and Anschauung are ambiguous between the -ing and -ed senses and that Kant often appears to employ them in the latter sense (for a clear instance see B278). See also note 20 above. With regard to B202–3 it should also be noted that Kant appears to take the claim that perception is possible only through synthesis in accordance with the concept of a magnitude to entail the claim that all intuitions are magnitudes (which is, after all, what the principle of the Axioms of Intuition states).

  24. 24.

    See e.g. A163/B204: “On this successive synthesis of the productive imagination, in the generation of shapes, is grounded the mathematics of extension (geometry)”; see also A164–5/B205.

  25. 25.

    Cf. B151; see also B154, where Kant says that the synthesis of the productive imagination is what is necessary for having a “determinate intuition” (emphasis in original).

  26. 26.

    “As figurative, it [i.e. the synthesis of the productive imagination] is distinct from the intellectual synthesis without any imagination merely through the understanding” (B152).

  27. 27.

    See note 19 for a list of these.

  28. 28.

    Verzeichnen might be better translated as “noting”, “exhibiting” or “registering”. See Grimm 1854/1961, vol. 25, cols 2494–503; see also Bxxii, where Guyer/Wood render verzeichnen as “catalog”.

  29. 29.

    The preceding sentence makes clear that Kant’s topic is representation; specifically, the particular way in which extensive magnitudes are represented: “I call an extensive magnitude that in which the representation of the parts makes possible the representation of the whole (and therefore necessarily precedes the latter)” (A162/B203).

  30. 30.

    The qualification is needed to make room for the contribution of empirical synthesis, such as the synthesis of apprehension.

  31. 31.

    See Engstrom (2006:18–9). Longuenesse (1998a:199–242) also holds that the affection of sensibility by the understanding is a necessary condition of an empirical intuition’s having objective purport, but her articulation of this position differs from the one presented here.

  32. 32.

    It might be thought that this claim commits me to the view that, for Kant, there can be no sensations that are not intuitions; and, therefore, no sensible representations that are merely “modification[s] of [the subject’s] state” (A320/B376) without at the same time being representations of objects. My response is that, when Kant distinguishes sensations from intuitions and speaks of the former as the matter of intuition, he is not thereby committing himself to the view that there could be mere sensation without any spatiotemporal properties; mere matter without form, that is. His view might well be the following. Any sensible representation exhibits the formal properties of sensible representations, namely, spatiotemporal properties. But among sensible representations we can distinguish two species: mere sensations, on the one hand, and intuitions, on the other. The former are merely subjectively valid, the latter, objectively. The latter have sensations as their matter. So talk of sensation simpliciter is indeterminate with regard to the representational species to which it refers: a sensation is either a mere sensation or it is an intuition. For helpful discussion see McDowell (2009:108–26). Note also that the view articulated in the text is compatible with the claim at B208 that sensation an sich is neither spatially nor temporally extended. For the context of the passage makes clear that sensation in this sense is a mere abstraction. So the claim does not imply that qua matter of empirical intuition sensations are not in time or space.

  33. 33.

    In this sense of “determine”, a receptive capacity is one that is determined from without, while a spontaneous capacity is one that is self-determining. Compare Kant’s claim, at B151–2, that spontaneity is “determining”, whereas sense is “merely determinable”; see also A373, where Kant speaks of an object’s determining sense by way of sensation, and B277n. Note that it is clear that the sense of “determine” here cannot be the “epistemic” sense, according to which an object is determined with respect to some predicate just in case a thinker represents the object as having that predicate (see Stang 2012:1128). For there would be no point in characterising the senses—as opposed to, say, objects sensed—as determinable if this was meant in the epistemic sense.

  34. 34.

    See B160 and A268/B324. So what Onof and Schulting (2015:6) refer to as “the standard interpretation” of the notion of formal intuition, according to which a formal intuition is distinguished from the mere form of intuition by being “determined” in a judgement (that is, brought under some concept in a judgement), is false. It rests on ignoring the doctrine of the a priori determination of sensibility by the understanding.

  35. 35.

    The nonconceptualist will of course insist that this last inference is not warranted because the synthesis of apprehension concerns, not empirical intuition, but rather perception, which is a distinct act of the mind from empirical intuition. But at this juncture in the dialectic the issue is whether or not the moderately conceptualist position is committed to seeing Kant as a sense atomist. To rebut this charge it is not necessary to provide independent grounds for the falsity of nonconceptualism. We are entitled to assume the moderately conceptualist reading.

  36. 36.

    See B154: “Inner sense, on the contrary, contains the mere form of intuition, but without combination of the manifold in it, and thus it does not yet contain any determinate intuition at all, which is possible only through the consciousness of the determination of the manifold through the transcendental action of the imagination (synthetic influence of the understanding on the inner sense), which I have named the figurative synthesis”.

  37. 37.

    For a different reading of this passage than the one that follows, see Tolley (2013:122–3).

  38. 38.

    Guyer/Wood have “moment” where I have “instant”. The German is Augenblick. This is significant because Augenblick is also the word used in the passage from A169/B211 quoted in the footnote below, which offers an explanation of Kant’s usage of the term. In that passage Guyer/Wood have “instant”, so for the sake of consistency I have opted for “instant” in both passages.

  39. 39.

    This is made explicit in the following passage: “The property of magnitudes on account of which no part of them is the smallest (no part is simple) is called their continuity. Space and time are quanta continua, because no part of them can be given except as enclosed between boundaries (points and instants), thus only in such a way that this part itself is in turn a space or a time. Space therefore consists only of spaces, time of times. Points and instants are only boundaries, i.e., mere places of their limitation; but places always presuppose those intuitions that they are supposed to limit or determine” (A169/B211; trans. amended, emphasis added). Guyer/Wood translate “that limit or determine them” where I have “that they are supposed to limit or determine”. The original is “die sie beschränken oder bestimmen sollen”. Both translations are grammatically possible, but it should be clear that e.g. a point is a limitation of the intuition of space rather than the intuition of space being a limitation of a point.

  40. 40.

    Note that the passage is preceded by a “general remark” on which, Kant says, “one must ground everything that follows” and which says that, qua modifications of the mind, all representations belong to inner sense and are therefore subject to the “formal condition” of inner sense, which is time (A98–9).

  41. 41.

    Note that Kant’s talk of sensibility’s “original receptivity” in the passage from A99–100 quoted in the preceding paragraph might be taken as additional evidence, since it might be taken to suggest a distinction between original and derivative receptivity. Sensibility’s original receptivity would be the receptiveness to its a priori determination by the understanding. Sensibility’s derivative receptivity would be its receptiveness to affection by objects in empirical intuition, which presupposes the a priori determination. In terms of this distinction, the charge of sense atomism rests on confounding original and derivative receptivity.

  42. 42.

    It might be thought that on the moderately conceptualist view there is no longer any robust sense in which intuition is given, since according to this view intuition depends on synthesis. But this is unwarranted. The moderate conceptualist allows for givenness in intuition at two levels, each of which is sufficiently robust. With regard to pure intuition, the character of the sensible manifold—for instance, the fact that it has three-plus-one dimensions—is independent of synthesis. The same goes for the fact that there is an “original” manifold to be synthesised, which for the moderate conceptualist amounts to saying that the character of the pure intuitions of space and time cannot be derived from the pure concepts of the understanding and is therefore not brought about by synthesis. With regard to empirical intuition, synthesis does not determine what is apprehended as unified; that is, what kind of object and which sensible qualities. Synthesis merely determines that these are apprehended as objects and as sensible qualities. That is, synthesis is responsible for the fact that an intuition is a representation of an object (in the sense in which the moderate conceptualist takes this phrase).

  43. 43.

    Thanks to Steve Engstrom for bringing the point in parentheses to my attention.

  44. 44.

    There are, however, good reasons for thinking that as a general characterisation of finite spontaneous representation this cannot be correct. See Land (2014a).

  45. 45.

    A162–3/B202–4; A169–70/B211–12. For discussion see Sutherland (2005a).

  46. 46.

    Cf. the doctrine of “motion, as action of the subject” (B154–5). For discussion see Friedman (1992:74–8). We can see here one respect in which the two forms of intuition, space and time, are interdependent: spatial representing, for Kant, is necessarily extended in time.

  47. 47.

    “I call an extensive magnitude that in which the representation of the parts makes possible the representation of the whole (and therefore necessarily precedes the latter). I cannot represent to myself any line, no matter how small it may be, without drawing it in thought, i.e., successively generating all its parts from one point, and thereby first sketching this intuition” (A162–3/B203).

Bibliography

  • Allais, Lucy. 2009. Kant, Non-Conceptual Content and the Representation of Space. Journal of the History of Philosophy 47(3): 383–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Manifest Reality: Kant’s Idealism and His Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Allison, H 2004. Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. An Interpretation and Defense. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engstrom, S. 2006. Understanding and Sensibility. Inquiry 49(1): 2–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1992. Kant and the Exact Sciences. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P 1969. What Do We Think With? In God and the Soul, ed. P. Geach, 30–41. New York: Schocken.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsborg, H 2008. Was Kant a Nonconceptualist? Philosophical Studies 137(1): 65–77 [also published in D. Heidemann (2013), pp. 208–18.].

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golob, S. 2014. Kant on Intentionality, Magnitude, and the Unity of Perception. European Journal of Philosophy 22(4): 505–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffith, A. 2012. Perception and the Categories: A Conceptualist Reading of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. European Journal of Philosophy 20(2): 193–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne, S 2009. Blinde Anschauung. Die Rolle von Begriffen in Kants Theorie sinnlicher Synthesis. Frankfurt a/M: Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R 2005. Kant and Nonconceptual Content. European Journal of Philosophy 13(2): 247–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2008. Kantian Non-Conceptualism. Philosophical Studies 137(1): 41–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2011b. Kant’s Non-Conceptualism, Rogue Objects, and the Gap in the B Deduction. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19(3): 399–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Land, T 2014a. Spatial Representation, Magnitude and the Two Stems of Cognition. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44(5/6): 524–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2015a. Nonconceptualist Readings of Kant and the Transcendental Deduction. Kantian Review 20(1): 25–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2015b. No Other Use Than in Judgment? Kant on Concepts and Sensible Synthesis. Journal of the History of Philosophy 53(3): 461–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2016. Conceptualism and the Objection from Animals. In Akten des 12. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longuenesse, B. 1998a. Kant and the Capacity to Judge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J 1998. Having the World in View: Sellars, Kant and Intentionality. [The Woodbridge Lectures]. Journal of Philosophy 95(9): 431–491.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2009. Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLear, C 2014b. The Kantian (Non)-Conceptualism Debate. Philosophy Compass 9(11): 769–790.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2015. Two Kinds of Unity in the Critique of Pure Reason. Journal of the History of Philosophy 53(1): 79–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Onof, C., and D. Schulting. 2015. Space as Form of Intuition and as Formal Intuition: On the Note to B160 in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. Philosophical Review 124(1): 1–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pippin, R. 1982. Kant’s Theory of Form: An Essay on the ‘Critique of Pure Reason’. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulting, D 2015b. Probleme des “kantianischen” Nonkonzeptualismus im Hinblick auf die B-Deduktion. Kant-Studien 106(4): 561–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W 1967. Some Remarks on Kant’s Theory of Experience. Journal of Philosophy 64(20): 633–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 1976. Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. In Kant’s Transcendental Metaphysics, eds. J. Sicha and W. Sellars, 403–417. Atascadero: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 1978. The Role of Imagination in Kant’s Theory of Experience. In Categories: A Colloquium, ed. H. Johnstone, 231–245. University Park, PA: Penn State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stang, N 2012. Kant on Complete Determination and Infinite Judgement. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20(6): 1117–1139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutherland, D. 2005a. The Point of Kant’s Axioms of Intuition. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86(1): 135–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tolley, C. 2013. The Non-Conceptuality of the Content of Intuitions: A New Approach. Kantian Review 18(1): 107–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Land .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2016 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Land, T. (2016). Moderate Conceptualism and Spatial Representation. In: Schulting, D. (eds) Kantian Nonconceptualism. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-53517-7_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics