Skip to main content

Digital Afterlives

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Palgrave Handbook of the Afterlife

Part of the book series: Palgrave Frontiers in Philosophy of Religion ((PFPR))

Abstract

Digitalists base their thoughts about reality on concepts taken from the sciences of information and computation. For digitalists, these sciences are prior to the physical sciences. Digitalists emphatically reject substance metaphysics. They are neither materialists nor idealists nor dualists. They have their own novel definitions of bodies, minds, lives, and souls. They talk about digital universes running on digital gods, and they regard nature as a recursively self-improving system of computations. They endorse digitized theories of resurrection and reincarnation. But they also argue for deeper and more mathematical approaches to life after death. All these digital ideas are naturalistic. They are consistent with our best sciences

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Digitalism is inspired by the classical digitalists, namely, Ed Fredkin, Hans Moravec, Frank Tipler, and Ray Kurzweil.

  2. 2.

    The inverse of uploading is promotion (Moravec, 1988: 152–3; Bostrom, 2003: 254). While uploading transfers a person from hardware to software, promotion transfers a person from software to hardware. The philosophical issues are the same.

  3. 3.

    Scanning in discussions of uploading is destructive; this is not the same as scanning in Parfit’s “branch-line” teleportation example (1985: 199–201).

  4. 4.

    The classical digitalists often discuss persistence (Moravec, 1988: 116–20; Tipler, 1995: 227–40; Kurzweil, 2005: 383–6). Their discussions of persistence are most compatible with four-dimensionalism (see Steinhart, 2014: ch. 2).

  5. 5.

    One estimate of the complexity of the body comes from Sagan (1995: 987). He says the human body contains about 1014 cells; but each cell encodes about 1012 bits of information; hence the body contains about 1026 bits. Another estimate comes from quantum mechanics. Moravec (2000: 166) uses quantum mechanical principles to show that any body contains at most about 1045 bits.

  6. 6.

    The classical digitalists all reject mind-body dualism. Moravec says “mind is entirely the consequence of interacting matter” (1988: 119; 2000: 121–4). Tipler rejects dualism: “a human being is a purely physical object, a biochemical machine completely and exhaustively described by the known laws of physics” (1995: 1). Kurzweil rejects dualism (1999: 55–65; Kurzweil, 2002: 191–4). He says that consciousness “does not require a world outside the physical world we experience” (2002: 214).

  7. 7.

    Leibniz identifies perfection with quantity of essence (Leibniz, 1697; Rutherford, 1995: 23). But the quantity of essence of some thing is its harmony, which is proportional to order and variety (Rutherford, 1995: 13, 35). Hence perfection is proportional to both variety and order (Monadology, sec 58; Rescher, 1979: 28–31). Thus the best universe-plan (the best cabinet) maximizes both variety and order (Principles of Nature and Grace, sec. 10; Discourse on Metaphysics, secs. 5–6).

  8. 8.

    For example, suppose a cabinet contains biographies A and B. Their improved versions are A1, A2, B1, and B2. But these improvements are designed together to ensure mutual compossibility. Hence there are eight improved cabinets {A1, B}, {A2, B}, {A1, B1}, {A2, B1}, {A1, B2}, {A2, B2}, {A, B1}, {A, B2}.

  9. 9.

    Hartshorne argues that an unsurpassable person is as absurd as an unsurpassble number (1965: 27; 1984: 7). Rather than depicting God as an unsurpassable person, he depicts God as an unsurpassable series of self-surpassing persons (1948: 20). Digitalists depict God as an unsurpassable hierarchy of self-surpassing computers.

References

  • Barrow, J. & Tipler, F. (1986) The Anthropic Cosmological Principle. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, C. (1988) Logical depth and physical complexity. In R. Herken (Ed.) (1988) The Universal Turing Machine: A Half-Century Survey. New York: Oxford University Press, 227–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, C. (1990) How to define complexity in physics, and why. In W. Zurek (Ed.) (1990) Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 137–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackford, R. & Broderick, D. (Eds.) (2014) Intelligence Unbound: The Future of Uploaded and Machine Minds. Malden, MA: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bostrom, N. (2003) Are you living in a computer simulation? Philosophical Quarterly 53 (211), 243–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burks, A. (1973) Logic, computers, and men. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 46, 39–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2010) The Singularity: A philosophical analysis. Journal of Consciousness Studies 17, 7–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Muzio, G. (2013) Reincarnation and infinite punishment in hell. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 74, 167–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, T. (2008) Moral enhancement. Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (3), 228–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faust, H. (2008) Should we select for moral enhancement? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29, 397–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Filice, C. (2006) The moral case for reincarnation. Religious Studies 42 (1), 45–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, B. (1771) The Autobiography. In A. Houston (ed.) (2004) The Autobiography and other Writings on Politics, Economics, and Virtue. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fredkin, E. (1992) Finite nature. In Proceedings of the XXVIIth Rencontre de Moriond. Gif-Sur-Yvette, France: Editions Frontieres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fredkin, E. (2003) An introduction to digital philosophy. International Journal of Theoretical Physics 42 (2), 189–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. (1965) Speculations concerning the first ultraintelligent machine. In Alt, F. & Rubinoff, M. (Eds.) Advances in Computers, Vol. 6. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamkins, J. (2002) Infinite time Turing machines. Minds and Machines 12 (4), 521–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1948) Divine Relativity: A Social Conception of God. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1965) Anselm’s Discovery: A Re-Examination of the Ontological Argument for God’s Existence. LaSalle, IL: Open Court Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1984) Omnipotence and Other Theological Mistakes. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2001) How Things Persist. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hick, J. (1976) Death and Eternal Life. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kardec, A. (1857) The Spirits’ Book. Miami, FL: Edicei of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaufman, W. (2005) Karma, rebirth, and the problem of evil. Philosophy East and West 55 (1), 15–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koepke, P. (2005) Turing computations on ordinals. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11, 377–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koepke, P. & Siders, R. (2008) Register computations on ordinals. Archive for Mathematical Logic 47, 529–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraay, K. (2010) The problem of no best world. In C. Taliaferro, P. Draper, & P. Quinn (Eds.) (2010) A Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 482–90.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kurzweil, R. (1999) The Age of Spiritual Machines. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurzweil, R. (2002) Replies to critics. In J. Richards (Ed.) (2002) Are We Spiritual Machines? Ray Kurzweil vs. The Critics of Strong AI. Seattle, WA: The Discovery Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurzweil, R. (2005) The Singularity is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1697/1988) On the ultimate origination of the universe. In P. Schrecker & A. Schrecker (1988) Leibniz: Monadology and Other Essays. New York: Macmillan Publishing, 84–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1703) Explication de l’arithmetique binaire. Memoires de l’Academie Royale des Sciences 3, 85–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1968) Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic. Journal of Philosophy 65, 113–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1976) Survival and identity. In A. O. Rorty (Ed.), The Identities of Persons. Berekeley, CA: University of California Press, 17–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986) On the Plurality of Worlds. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machta, J. (2011) Natural complexity, computational complexity, and depth. Chaos 21, 037111–1 to 037111–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackay, D. (1997) Computer software and life after death. In P. Edwards (Ed.) Immortality. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 248–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millican, P. (2004) The one fatal flaw in Anselm’s argument. Mind 113, 451–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moravec, H. (1988) Mind Children: The Future of Robot and Human Intelligence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moravec, H. (2000) Robot: Mere Machine to Transcendent Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1985) Reasons and Persons. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne, J. C. (1985) The scientific worldview and a destiny beyond death. In G. MacGregor (ed.) Immortality and Human Destiny: A Variety of Views. New York: Paragon House, 180–3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahula, W. (1974) What the Buddha Taught. New York: Grove /Atlantic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, B. (1978) Monism and the possibility of life after death. Religious Studies 14 (1), 27–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1979) Leibniz: An Introduction to his Philosophy. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1991) G. W. Leibniz’s Monadology: An Edition for Students. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (2010) Axiogenesis: An Essay in Metaphysical Optimalism. New York: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutherford, D. (1995) Leibniz and the Rational Order of Nature. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, J. (1996) Leibniz’ binary system and Shao Yong’s “Yijing”. Philosophy East and West 46 (1), 59–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sagan, C. (1995) Life. Encyclopedia Britannica 22, 985–1002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidhuber, J. (2007) Godel machines: Fully self-referential optimal universal self-improvers. In B. Goertzel & C. Pennachin (Eds.) (2007) Artificial General Intelligence. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 199–226.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (1996) All the world’s a stage. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, 433–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001) Four-Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steinhart, E. (2004) Pantheism and current ontology. Religious Studies 40 (1), 63–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinhart, E. (2008) The revision theory of resurrection. Religious Studies 44 (1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinhart, E. (2013) On the plurality of gods. Religious Studies 49 (3), 289–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinhart, E. (2014) Your Digital Afterlives: Computational Theories of Life after Death. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strickland, L. (2006) Leibniz Reinterpreted. New York: Continuum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swenson, R. (1997) Evolutionary theory developing: The problem(s) with Darwin’s Dangerous Idea. Ecological Psychology 9 (1), 47–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tipler, F. (1995) The Physics of Immortality: Modern Cosmology, God and the Resurrection of the Dead. New York: Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eric Steinhart .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Steinhart, E. (2017). Digital Afterlives. In: Nagasawa, Y., Matheson, B. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of the Afterlife. Palgrave Frontiers in Philosophy of Religion. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-48609-7_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics