Skip to main content

The Relevance of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy to Psychology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Wittgenstein’s Philosophy in Psychology
  • 715 Accesses

Abstract

The nature of the relevance and relation of Wittgenstein’s philosophy to psychology is examined in this chapter starting with general issues surrounding the relations between philosophy and science, and highlighting misleading pictures and comparisons identified by Wittgenstein in relation to psychology’s supposed status, unlike physics, as a “young science”. A Wittgensteinian perspective is developed about pernicious and positive forms of reflexivity, respectively, arguing that Wittgenstein’s later philosophy is not postmodern or self-referentially inconsistent and showing that psychology can be fruitfully compared with mathematics. The game analogy of psychology is used to avoid the problems of constructing metatheories about social and psychological science, clarify the role of theoretical psychology, and outline the importance of achieving a surview of the grammar of psychological and metapsychological concepts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Averill, J. R. (1992). The structural bases of emotional behavior: A metatheoretical analysis. In M. S. Clark (Ed.), Review of personality and social psychology, 13: Emotion (pp. 1–24). Newbury Park, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Averill, J. R. (2012). The future of social constructionism. Emotion Review, 4(3), 215–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (1980). Wittgenstein: Understanding and meaning (Vol. 1). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (1985). Wittgenstein: Rules, grammar and necessity (Vol. 2). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, P. (1989). The reflexivity problem in the psychology of science. In B. Gholson, W. R. Shadish Jr., R. A. Neimeyer, & A. C. Houts (Eds.), Psychology of science: Contributions to metascience (pp. 92–114). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (1988). Philosophy of science: An overview for cognitive science. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bem, S. (2001). The explanatory autonomy of psychology: Why a mind is not a brain. Theory & Psychology, 11(6), 785–795.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bem, S., & Looren de Jong, H. (1997). Theoretical issues in psychology (1st ed.). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Cambridge, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertens, H. (1995). The Idea of the postmodern: A history. Abingdon, UK: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Billig, M. (1995). Banal nationalism. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1976). Knowledge and social imagery. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1997). Wittgenstein on rules and institutions. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (2004). Science of science and reflexivity. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouveresse, J. (1995). Wittgenstein reads Freud: The myth of the unconscious (C. Cosman, Trans.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Budd, M. (1989). Wittgenstein’s philosophy of psychology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2000). Philosophy from the outside. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 30(2), 227–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buss, A. R. (1978). The structure of psychological revolutions. Journal of the History of the Behavioural Sciences, 14(1), 57–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. M. (1995). Evolutionary psychology: A new paradigm for psychological science. Psychological Inquiry, 6(1), 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chmielski, A. J., & Popper, K. R. (1999). The future is open: A conversation with Sir Karl Popper. In I. C. Jarvie & S. Pralong (Eds.), Popper’s Open Society after fifty years: The continuing relevance of Karl Popper (pp. 28–38). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1988). Matter and consciousness (Rev. ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2009). What language does to feelings. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16(9), 4–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2014). The feeling body: Affective sciences meets the enactive mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coulter, J. (1989). Mind in action. Cambridge, MA: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coulter, J. (1999). Discourse and mind. Human Studies, 22(2), 163–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Back Bay Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1996). Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1989). The passions of the soul (S. Voss, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. (Original work published 1649)

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, C. (Ed.). (1976). Wittgenstein’s lectures on the foundations of mathematics, Cambridge 1939. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver-Linn, E. (2003). Where is psychology going? Structural fault lines revealed by psychologists’ use of Kuhn. American Psychologist, 58(4), 269–278.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Edmonds, D., & Eidinow, J. (2001). Wittgenstein’s poker. The story of a ten-minute argument between two great philosophers. London: Faber & Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, D. (1997). Discourse and cognition. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, D., & Potter, J. (1992). Discursive psychology. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finch, H. L. (1995). Wittgenstein. Dorset, UK: Element.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (1981). Psychology, progress, and the problem of reflexivity: A study in the epistemological foundations of psychology. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 17(3), 375–386.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Garver, N., & Lee, S.-C. (1994). Derrida and Wittgenstein. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gellner, E. (1959). Words and things: A critical account of linguistic philosophy and a study in ideology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gergen, K. J. (1985). The social constructionist movement in modern psychology. American Psychologist, 40(3), 266–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gergen, K. J. (1987). Introduction: Towards metapsychology. In H. J. Stam, T. B. Rogers, & K. J. Gergen (Eds.), The analysis of psychological theory: Metapsychological perspectives (pp. 1–21). Washington, DC: Hemisphere.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gergen, K. J. (1994). Realities and relationships. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gergen, K. J. (1999). An invitation to social constructionism. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gergen, K. J. (2001a). Psychological science in a postmodern context. American Psychologist, 56(10), 803–813.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Gergen, K. J. (2001b). Construction in contention: Toward consequential resolutions. Theory & Psychology, 11(3), 419–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H.-J. (1996). A Wittgenstein dictionary. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood, J. D. (1991). Relations and representations: An introduction to the philosophy of social psychological science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gustafsson, Y., Kronqvist, C., & McEachrane, M. (Eds.). (2009). Emotions and understanding: Wittgensteinian perspectives. London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (1996a). Wittgenstein’s place in twentieth-century analytic philosophy. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (1996b). Wittgenstein: Mind and will (Vol. 4). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (2004). The conceptual framework for the investigation of emotions. International Review of Psychiatry, 16(3), 199–208.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (2012). The relevance of Wittgenstein’s philosophy of psychology to the psychological sciences. In P. Stekeler-Weithofer (Ed.), Wittgenstein: Zu Philosophie und Wissenschaft (pp. 205–223). Hamburg, Germany: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1995). The looping effects of human kinds. In D. Sperber & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition (pp. 351–383). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haig, B. D. (2008). How to enrich scientific method. American Psychologist, 63(6), 565–566.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1986). An outline of the social constructionist viewpoint. In R. Harré (Ed.), The social construction of emotions (pp. 2–14). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1988). Wittgenstein and artificial intelligence. Philosophical Psychology, 1(1), 105–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1989a). Language and the science of psychology. Journal of Social Behavior and Personality, 4(3), 165–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1989b). Metaphysics and methodology: Some prescriptions for social psychological research. European Journal of Social Psychology, 19(5), 439–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1992). What is real in psychology: A plea for persons. Theory & Psychology, 2(2), 153–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (2007). Wittgenstein and the foundations of cognitive psychology. In D. Moyal-Sharrock (Ed.), Perspicuous presentations: Essays on Wittgenstein’s philosophy of psychology (pp. 114–127). London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., & Gillett, G. (1994). The discursive mind. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., & Tissaw, M. (2005). Wittgenstein and psychology: A practical guide. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hergenhahn, B. R. (2001). An introduction to the history of psychology (4th ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Thomson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hibberd, F. J. (2001a). Gergen’s social constructionism, logical positivism and the continuity of error. Part 1: Conventionalism. Theory & Psychology, 11(3), 297–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hibberd, F. J. (2001b). Gergen’s social constructionism, logical positivism and the continuity of error: Part 2: Meaning-as-use. Theory & Psychology, 11(3), 323–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hibberd, F. J. (2005). Unfolding social constructionism. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hochschild, A. R. (1990). Ideology and emotion management: A perspective and path for future research. In T. D. Kemper (Ed.), Research agendas in the sociology of emotions (pp. 117–142). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holzman, L., & Morss, J. (Eds.). (2000). Postmodern psychologies, societal practice, and political life. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, C. A. (1987). A realistic theory of science. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, G. S. (1985). The role of values in the science of psychology. American Psychologist, 40(3), 255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, P., & Read, R. (2008). Toward a perspicuous presentation of “perspicuous presentation”. Philosophical Investigations, 31(2), 141–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2013). Psychology’s inescapable need for conceptual clarification. In T. P. Racine & K. L. Slaney (Eds.), A Wittgensteinian perspective on the use of conceptual analysis in psychology (pp. 28–50). Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jost, J. T. (1995). Toward a Wittgensteinian social psychology of human development. Theory & Psychology, 5(1), 5–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kemper, T. D. (1990). Themes and variations in the sociology of emotions. In T. D. Kemper (Ed.), Research agendas in the sociology of emotions (pp. 3–23). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1929). Gestalt psychology. New York: H. Liveright.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2015). The affective ‘we’: Self-regulation and shared emotions. In T. Szanto & D. Moran (Eds.), The phenomenology of sociality: Discovering the ‘we’ (pp. 263–277). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, H. (1987). Reflexivity: The post-modern predicament. London: Hutchison.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lock, A., & Strong, T. (2010). Social constructionism: Sources and stirrings in theory and practice. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lyotard, J.-F. (1984). The postmodern condition: A report on knowledge. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machado, A., & Silva, F. J. (2007). Toward a richer view of the scientific method: The role of conceptual analysis. American Psychologist, 62(7), 671–681.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Madill, A., & Gough, B. (2008). Qualitative research and its place in psychological science. Psychological Methods, 13(3), 254–271.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Mason, W. A., & Capitanio, J. P. (2012). Basic emotions: A reconstruction. Emotion Review, 4(3), 238–244.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • McEachrane, M. (2009). Emotion, meaning, and appraisal theory. Theory & Psychology, 19(1), 33–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monk, R. (1990). Ludwig Wittgenstein: The duty of genius. London: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, K. (2000). ‘Going nowhere’ with Wittgenstein: And staying in the everyday. Theory & Psychology, 10(2), 214–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moyal-Sharrock, D. (2004). Understanding Wittgenstein’s on certainty. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moyal-Sharrock, D. (Ed.). (2007). Perspicuous presentations: Essays on Wittgenstein’s philosophy of psychology. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyal-Sharrock, D. (2013). Realism, but not empiricism: Wittgenstein versus Searle. In T. P. Racine, K. L. Slaney, & K. L. (Eds.), A Wittgensteinian perspective on the use of conceptual analysis in psychology (pp. 153–171). Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, M. (2001). Explaining ‘The hardness of the logical must’: Wittgenstein on grammar, arbitrariness and logical necessity. Philosophical Investigations, 24(1), 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oatley, K. (1993). Social construction in emotions. In M. Lewis & J. M. Haviland (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (pp. 341–352). New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, W. D., & Landfield, A. W. (1962). Reflexivity: An unfaced issue of psychology. Journal of Individual Psychology, 18(2), 114–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paley, J. (2008). Empiricism. In L. M. Given (Ed.), The SAGE encyclopedia of qualitative research methods (pp. 255–259). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, I. (1989). The crisis in modern social psychology: And how to end it. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, I. (1996). Against Wittgenstein: Materialist reflections on language in psychology. Theory & Psychology, 6(3), 363–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parkinson, B. (1995). Ideas and realities of emotions. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parkinson, B. (2012). Piecing together emotion: Sites and time-scales for social construction. Emotion Review, 4(3), 291–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D. L. (1977). Wittgenstein and scientific knowledge: A sociological perspective. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (2013). The open society and its enemies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potter, J. (2001). Wittgenstein and Austin. In M. Wetherell, S. Taylor, & S. Yates (Eds.), Discourse theory and practice (pp. 39–46). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potter, J., & Edwards, D. (2003). Rethinking cognition: On Coulter on discourse and mind. Human Studies, 26(2), 165–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, M. (2004). Set theory and its philosophy: An introduction. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Racine, T. P., & Müller, U. (2009). The contemporary relevance of Wittgenstein: Reflections and directions. New Ideas in Psychology, 27(2), 307–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Racine, T. P., & Slaney, K. L. (Eds.). (2013). A Wittgensteinian perspective on the use of conceptual analysis in psychology. London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, R. (2012). Wittgenstein among the Sciences: Wittgensteinian investigations into the “scientific method” (S. Summers, Ed.). London: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E. (1987). Wittgenstein and categorization research in cognitive psychology. In M. Chapman & R. A. Dixon (Eds.), Meaning and the growth of understanding (pp. 151–166). Berlin, Germany: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E., & Mervis, C. B. (1975). Family resemblances: Studies in the internal structure of categories. Cognitive Psychology, 7(4), 573–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rundle, B. (1995). Analytical philosophy and psychology. In J. A. Smith, R. Harré, & L. V. Langenhove (Eds.), Rethinking psychology (pp. 207–221). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulte, J. (1993). Experience and expression: Wittgenstein’s philosophy of psychology. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanker, S. G. (1991). The enduring relevance of Wittgenstein’s remarks on intentions. In J. Hyman (Ed.), Investigating psychology: Sciences of mind after Wittgenstein (pp. 67–94). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanker, S. G. (1993). Wittgenstein versus James and Russell on the nature of willing. In S. Shanker & J. Canfield (Eds.), Wittgenstein’s intentions (pp. 195–243). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shotter, J. (1990). Wittgenstein and psychology: On our ‘hook up’ to reality. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 28, 193–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shotter, J. (1992a). ‘Getting in touch’: The meta-methodology of a postmodern science of mental life. In S. Kvale (Ed.), Psychology and postmodernism (pp. 58–73). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shotter, J. (1992b). Social constructionism and realism: Adequacy or accuracy? Theory & Psychology, 2(2), 175–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shotter, J. (1993a). Cultural politics of everyday life: Social constructionism, rhetoric and knowing of the third kind. Buckingham, UK: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shotter, J. (1993b). Conversational realities: Constructing life through language. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shotter, J. (1993c). Harré, Vygotsky, Bakhtin, Vico, Wittgenstein: Academic discourses and conversational realities. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 23(4), 459–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shotter, J. (1996a). Living in a Wittgensteinian world: Beyond theory to a poetics of practices. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 26(3), 293–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shotter, J. (1996b). Wittgenstein in practice: From the way of theory to a social poetics. In C. W. Tolman, F. Cherry, R. van Hezewijk, & I. Lubek (Eds.), Problems of theoretical psychology (pp. 27–34). North York, Canada: Captus Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shotter, J. (1996c). ‘Now I can go on’: Wittgenstein and our embodied embeddedness in the ‘Hurly-Burly’ of life. Human Studies, 19(4), 385–407.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shotter, J. (2016). Undisciplining social science: Wittgenstein and the art of creating situated practices of social inquiry. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 46, 60–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slife, B. D., & Williams, R. N. (1997). Toward a theoretical psychology: Should a subdiscipline be formally recognized? American Psychologist, 52(2), 117–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smedslund, J. (1985). Necessarily true cultural psychologies. In K. J. Gergen & K. E. Davis (Eds.), The social construction of the person (pp. 73–87). Berlin, Germany: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smedslund, J. (1988). Psycho-logic. Berlin, Germany: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smedslund, J. (1990). Psychology and psychologic: Characterization of the difference. In R. Semin & K. J. Gergen (Eds.), Everyday understanding: Social and scientific implications (pp. 45–65). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smedslund, J. (1995). Psychologic: Common sense and the pseudoempirical. In J. A. Smith, R. Harré, & L. Van Langenhove (Eds.), Rethinking psychology (pp. 196–206). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staats, A. W. (1991). Unified positivism and unification psychology: Fad or new field? American Psychologist, 46, 899–912.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Staten, H. (1984). Wittgenstein and Derrida. Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strom, A. (1994). Moore and Wittgenstein on certainty. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, G. B. (2000). Wittgenstein and social constructionism: “Methods of social poetics” or “knots in our thinking”? In J. Morss, N. Stephenson, & H. van Rappard (Eds.), Theoretical issues in psychology. Proceedings of the International Society for Theoretical Psychology 1999 conference (pp. 181–193). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, G. B. (2002). Reflexivity and subjectivity in qualitative research: The utility of a Wittgensteinian framework. Forum: Qualitative Social Research, 3(3). Retrieved from: http://www.qualitative-research.net/index.php/fqs/article/view/833

  • Sullivan, G. B. (2005). Wittgenstein and the conversational model. In R. Meares & P. Nolan (Eds.), The self in conversation (Vol. 4, pp. 49–58). Sydney, Australia: ANZAP Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, G. B. (2007). Wittgenstein and the grammar of pride: The relevance of philosophy to studies of self-evaluative emotions. New Ideas in Psychology, 25(3), 233–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, G. B. (2009). Wittgenstein, reflexivity and the social construction of reality. In V. A. Munz, K. Puhl, & J. Wang (Eds.), Language and world. Papers of the 32nd international Wittgenstein symposium (Vol. 17, pp. 395–397). Kirchberg am Wechsel: Department for Culture and Science of the Province of Lower Austria.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, G. B. (Ed.). (2014). Understanding collective pride and group identity: New directions in emotion theory, research and practice. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, G. B. (2015). Wittgenstein’s later philosophy and “pictures” of mixed-method research in psychology: A critical investigation of theories and accounts of methodological plurality. Theory & Psychology, 25(4), 473–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, G. B., & Strongman, K. T. (2003). Vacillating and mixed emotions: Exploration of a conceptual-discursive perspective through examples of pride. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 33(2), 201–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tejedor, C. (2015). The early Wittgenstein on metaphysics, natural Science, language and value. Abingdon, UK: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorne, B. M., & Henley, T. B. (2001). Connections in the history and systems of psychology. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trigg, R. (1991). Wittgenstein and social science. In A. P. Griffiths (Ed.), Wittgenstein centenary essays (pp. 209–222). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uschanov, T. P. (2002). Ernest Gellner’s criticisms of Wittgenstein and ordinary language philosophy. In G. Kitching & N. Pleasants (Eds.), Marx and Wittgenstein: Knowledge, morality and politics (pp. 23–46). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations (3rd ed., G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The blue and brown books. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Zettel (G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright, Eds., G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Philosophical grammar (R. Rhees, Ed., A. Kenny, Trans.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1975). Philosophical remarks (R. Rhees, Ed.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1978). Remarks on the foundations of mathematics (3rd ed.,G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees, & G. E. M. Anscombe, Eds., G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell. (First published 1956)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1979). On certainty (G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright, Eds., D. Paul & G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980a). Culture and value (G. H. von Wright, Ed., P. Winch, Trans.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980b). Remarks on the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 1) (G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright, Eds.,. G. E. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980c). Remarks on the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 2) (G. H. von Wright & H. Nyman, Eds., C. G. Luckhardt & M. A. E. Aue, Trans.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1990). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. (C. K. Ogden, Trans.). London: Routledge. (Original work published 1922)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Sullivan, G.B. (2017). The Relevance of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy to Psychology. In: Wittgenstein’s Philosophy in Psychology. Palgrave Studies in the Theory and History of Psychology. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-45691-5_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics