Skip to main content

Pluralism About Self-knowledge

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 444 Accesses

Part of the book series: Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy ((PIIP))

Abstract

The metaphysically robust constitutive account presented in the previous chapter cannot be extended to all mental states. When it comes to past self-ascriptions of commitments, it will have to be integrated with an evidential account resting on mnestic evidence. As to self-knowledge of sensations, basic emotions and perceptions, there appears to be room for a weaker kind of constitutive account, which abandons the metaphysical claim that self-ascriptions bring about the corresponding first-order mental states. Still, it is necessarily and a priori true that, given certain C-conditions, one is in one of these mental states iff one self-ascribes them. The key idea, here, is that these mental states are phenomenologically salient and have characteristic instinctive manifestations. Groundlessness, transparency and authority, then, are redeemed by showing how they are constitutively tied to what it means to be a subject capable of enjoying the relevant mental states. Finally, various cases of third-personal self-knowledge are reviewed. A variety of methods can be implemented with regard to them, like inference to the best explanation, as well as less theory-laden abductive explanations, inferential conceptual deployment, testimony and simulation. An aspect that sets third-personal self-knowledge apart from third-personal knowledge simpliciter is the fact that the relevant cues are often of a psychological nature and known in a first-personal way. Finally, it is emphasised how the characteristic notes of highly dispositional psychological concepts can make us realise (or sometimes contrive) some of our deep-seated character traits. All that testifies to the plurality of ways in which we do know the vast variety of mental states we in fact enjoy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In order to avoid thinking of self-ascriptions of past commitments as based on having in view one’s past mental states, it is useful to think of a subject who, having lost her mid- and long-term memory, keeps a very accurate diary of her daily activities. She could still make past self-ascriptions, yet in no sense would they be based on having in view one’s past mental states.

  2. 2.

    I think similar considerations can be put forward for self-ascriptions of ongoing thoughts, mental images and imagination.

  3. 3.

    To be clear, I do not wish to deny that sensations such as pain, pleasure, hunger, thirst, coldness and hotness have a distinctive phenomenology. What I do deny is that our concepts are tags we use by having learnt to identify the relevant sensations while having in view their distinctive phenomenology. Rather, these sensations have distinctive behavioural manifestations and we are taught to replace, or at least to accompany those behavioural manifestations with the relevant self-ascriptions. In contrast, I do think that the phenomenological account would be a non-starter in the case of propositional attitudes, for there does not seem to be anything phenomenologically salient in the mere propositional attitude (let it be of belief, or desire, or intention, and so on). If there is something phenomenologically relevant is the kind of feeligs which can accompany those propositional attitudes. Furthermore, it does not seem to me that phenomenology would help us distinguish among the various fine-grained propositional attitudes we may enjoy. For instance, I simply don’t see what could distinguish a hope from a wish at a merely phenomenological level.

  4. 4.

    This account seems to me largely in keeping with the gist of Evans’s account of our knowledge of our seemings, put forward in Evans (1982, chapter 7).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2016 The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Coliva, A. (2016). Pluralism About Self-knowledge. In: The Varieties of Self-Knowledge. Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-32613-3_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics