Skip to main content

Swords and Scabbards: Locke’s Occupation of Shaftesbury and Burke

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 248 Accesses

Abstract

In issue 409 of his renowned London daily The Spectator, Joseph Addison (1672–1719) hypes his imminent “Pleasures of the Imagination” by assuring his readers that he has something “entirely new” to say about “what it is that gives a Beauty to any Passages of the finest Writers both in Prose and Verse” (Addison and Steele 1891, vol. 2, p. 710; see also Stolnitz 1961, p. 188). There is reason to receive his claim of founding a new discipline as something more than hyperbole. The eighteenth century is distinguished as a robust repository of a heretofore suppressed and distracted aesthetic discourse (Cassirer 1955, p. 312). For the first time since Plotinus (204–70 AD), a systematic effort is undertaken to distinguish the essential attributes of beauty itself. The culmination, of course, is Immanuel Kant’s (1724–1804) Critique of Judgement (1892 [1790]). And aesthetics, finally, is thought to have a field of its own.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “The Germans are the only people who at present use this word to indicate what others call the critique of taste. At the foundation of this term lies the disappointed hope, which the eminent analyst, Baumgarten, conceived, of subjecting the criticism of the beautiful to principles of reason, and so elevating its rules into a science” (Kant 1943 [1781], p. 22 [Critique of Pure Reason, Part I, Introductory, note]).

  2. 2.

    Although I am indebted to Terry Eagleton for concentrating on the environmental influences on concepts like beauty, it will become clear that I do not accept his conviction that aesthetics is “ideology” in the Marxist sense. I think that complex permutations of “disinterest” are available, indeed indispensable, to humans, and that Marx and his successors are at their most challenged when confronting this issue. I should also say here that I am mystified by Eagleton’s claim in the Introduction of his The Ideology of the Aesthetic that “almost all of the thinkers I discuss in this book are in fact German, even if some of the concepts I bring to bear upon their work stem from the intellectual milieu of modern France” (1990, p. 2). Perhaps he had not yet conceived of his next chapter, “The Law of the Heart: Shaftesbury, Hume, Burke,” which sets the stage for his materialist interpretation of beauty.

  3. 3.

    White (2002) is one of the few to recognize the political implications of Burke’s aesthetic musings. He laments that even the bicentennial celebration of Burke’s Reflections (Blakemore 1992) is undertaken by literary, not political, theorists.

  4. 4.

    “Qu’est-ce qui peut le rendre légitime?” (Rousseau 1797, p. 3).

  5. 5.

    “If I consider him, in a word, such as he must have issued from the hands of nature; I see an animal less strong than some, and less agile than others, but, upon the whole, the most advantageously organized of any: I see him satisfying his hunger under an oak, and his thirst at the first brook; I see him laying himself down to sleep at the foot of the same tree that afforded him his meal; and there are all his wants completely supplied” (Rousseau 2002 [1755], p. 90 [Second Discourse 1]).

  6. 6.

    There is one reference to “the Temptation” (Locke 1988, p. 190 [1.5.44]).

  7. 7.

    “In all things of this kind there is little need or use of revelation, God having furnished us with natural and surer means to arrive at the knowledge of them.”

  8. 8.

    A superb essay (State 1985) questions the easy designation of atheism suggested by some of Hobbes’s peers, as well as by Quentin Skinner (1972).

  9. 9.

    I should admit that scholars continue to debate the extent to which Locke segregates reason from revelation, and the extent to which he embraces the latter (see Brown 1999).

  10. 10.

    Locke approaches playfulness, invoking a delicious ambiguity regarding human reason, which renders its aficionados “almost equal to Angels” (Locke 1988, p. 200 [1.6.58]).

  11. 11.

    I intentionally sidestep an important, but treacherous, debate regarding Locke’s piety (for a taste of its bitterness, see Yolton 1958). Here, I am arguing that he depends in unprecedented ways on the faculty of reason. I will leave it to Leo Strauss, John Dunn, and their respective adherents to specify just how much human reason owes to God. A superb inventory of such scholarship is undertaken in Rabieh (1991), where even Locke’s The Reasonableness of Christianity (1999 [1695]) is contemplated as a refutation of theistic natural law. Fortunately, Locke’s embrace of sense and reflection can be considered without entering the debate about his piety. Certainly that is how Shaftesbury, who is discussed below, undertakes his own critique of Locke.

  12. 12.

    Lawrence Klein, editor of Shaftesbury’s Characteristics, footnotes a letter of 3 June 1707, in which Shaftesbury explicitly makes the connection: “credulous Mr. Locke, with his Indian, barbarian stories of wild nations that have no such idea (as travelers, learned authors and men of truth and great philosophers have informed him)” (Shaftesbury 1999, p. 154, note EEEE), quoting Cooper (1716, pp. 39–40).

  13. 13.

    “The brain certainly is a great starver where it abounds, and the thinking people of the world, the philosophers and virtuosi especially, must be contented, I find, with a moderate share of bodily advantages for the sake of what they call parts and capacity in another sense.”

  14. 14.

    This helps explain the intriguing title of Shaftesbury’s essay, which promises advice to authors (Shaftesbury 1999, pp. 70–162).

  15. 15.

    “The main contentions of Burke’s essay on ‘The Sublime and the Beautiful’—owes little or nothing to L” (Russell 1964, p. xlv; see also Cronk 2002, pp. 77–117).

  16. 16.

    I will here only briefly indulge the nonetheless ambient temptation to discuss Kant. Despite scholarly efforts to distinguish him (see Townsend 1987), Kant is clearly seduced by the Burkean inclination to elevate the sublime to parity with the beautiful. Kant’s practical reason, based on the imposition of shared meanings on an inscrutable natural setting, is celebrated and elevated by classifying the reveling of its success as an experience that is just as rewarding as encountering a monumental poem would be. Kant embraces Shaftesbury’s circumscribed disinterestedness, with its hidden bias, thereby elevating the sublime to the status of the beautiful. He specifies the waterfall as particularly sublime. It is an aesthetic experience of great intensity because, while representing close up an overwhelming threat to survival, viewing it from a suitable distance allows a very pleasing nonchalance, or disinterest, to turn dread into a celebration of human accomplishment. The connection of disinterest to survival is clear. Kant’s substantiation and reinforcement of Shaftesbury’s reaction to Locke is a tribute to classical liberalism’s influence, an influence that is arguably strongest in America.

  17. 17.

    In 1793, the American geologist Robert McCauslin discovers that the rate of the Fall’s upstream retreat due to erosion is far too small to sustain the biblical account of Earth’s age (Gilbert 1907, p. 6).

  18. 18.

    The barrel, in fact, is eventually swindled from her, and a young man who some years later actually swims over the falls is far less celebrated.

References

  • Addison, Joseph, and Richard Steele. 1891. The Spectator. Edited by Henry Morley. 3 vols. London: George Routledge and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. 1983. What Is a Law of Nature? Cambridge, U.K.; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, Hugh. 1993. Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres. Delmar, NY: Scholars’ Facsimiles and Reprints.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, Steven, ed. 1992. Burke and the French Revolution: Bicentennial Essays. Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, Allan. 1988. The Closing of the American Mind. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Robert E. 1999. “Edwards, Locke, and the Bible.” The Journal of Religion 79 (3): 361–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burke, Edmund. 1955. Reflections on the Revolution in France. Edited by Thomas H. D. Mahoney. New York: Library of Liberal Arts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burke, Edmund. 1958. The Correspondence of Edmund Burke. Edited by Thomas W. Copeland. 10 vols. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burke, Edmund. 1998. A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful: And Other Pre-Revolutionary Writings. Edited by David Womersley. London; New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, William F. 2006. “Burke’s Higher Romanticism: Politics and the Sublime.” Humanitas 19 (1 and 2): 14–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, Daniel. 2006. Locke, Shaftesbury, and Hutcheson: Contesting Diversity in the Enlightenment and Beyond. Cambridge, U.K.; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, Stephen L. 2002. “The Circulation of Blair’s ‘Lectures.’” Rhetoric Society Quarterly 32 (4): 75–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, Ernst. 1955. The Philosophy of the Enlightenment. Translated by Fritz C. A. Koelln and James P. Pettegrove. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, Anthony Ashley Third Earl of Shaftesbury. 1716. Several Letters Written by a Noble Lord to a Young Man at the University. London: J. Roberts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cronk, Nicholas. 2002. The Classical Sublime: French Neoclassicism and the Language of Literature. Charlottesville, VA: Rockwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cronon, William. 1996. “The Trouble With Wilderness; or Getting Back to the Wrong Nature.” In Uncommon Ground: Rethinking the Human Place in Nature, by William Cronon, 66–90. New York: W.W. Norton and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Edward H. 1963. “From Locke to Edwards.” Journal of the History of Ideas 24 (3): 355–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickenson, Victoria. 1998. Drawn from Life: Science and Art in the Portrayal of the New World. Toronto, Ontario: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow, Charles Mason. 1921. Anthology and Bibliography of Niagara Falls. 2 vols. Albany, NY: J. B. Lyon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dussinger, John A. 1981. “‘The Lovely System of Lord Shaftesbury’: An Answer to Locke in the Aftermath of 1688?” Journal of the History of Ideas 42 (1): 151–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eagleton, Terry. 1990. The Ideology of the Aesthetic. Oxford, U.K.; Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filmer, Robert. 1949. Patriarcha and Other Political Works. Oxford, U.K.: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fowler, Thomas. 1882. Shaftesbury and Hutcheson. London: Sampson Low, Marston, Searle, and Rivington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, G. K. 1907. Rate of Recession of Niagara Falls. Washington, DC: Government Printing Office.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gracyk, Theodore A. 1986. “Kant’s Shifting Debt to British Aesthetics.” British Journal of Aesthetics 26 (Summer): 204–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haley, Kenneth Harold Dobson. 1968. The First Earl of Shaftesbury. Oxford, U.K.: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, Harold F. 1965. “Introduction.” In Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres, by Hugh Blair, vii – vlx. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartz, Louis. 1991. The Liberal Tradition in America: An Interpretation of American Political Thought since the Revolution. San Diego, CA: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitt, Christopher. 1999. “Toward an Ecological Sublime.” New Literary History 30 (3): 603–623.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1991. Leviathan. Cambridge, U.K.; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huth, Hans. 1991. Nature and the American: Three Centuries of Changing Attitudes. Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jefferson, Thomas. 1829. Notes on the State of Virginia. Boston, MA: Wells and Lilly.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1892. Kritik of Judgment. Translated by. J. H. Bernard. London: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel.1943. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by J. M. D. Meiklejohn. New York: Willey Book Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeller, Paul Oskar. 1952. “The Modern System of the Arts: A Study in the History of Aesthetics (II).” Journal of the History of Ideas 13 (1): 17–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaFreniere, Gilbert F. 1990. “Rousseau and the European Roots of Environmentalism.” Environmental History Review 14 (4): 41–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lane, Joseph H., Jr. 2006. “Reverie and the Return to Nature: Rousseau’s Experience of Convergence.” The Review of Politics 68 (3): 474–499.

    Google Scholar 

  • Letzter, Jacqueline, and Robert Adelson. 2000. “French Women Opera Composers and the Aesthetics of Rousseau.” Feminist Studies 26 (1): 69–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1813. “Elements of Natural Philosophy.” In An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. 2 vols., by John Locke, 2:373–413. London: Cummings and Hilliard and J. T. Buckingham.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1894. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1976. The Correspondence of John Locke. 8 vols. Edited by E. S. de Beer. Oxford, U.K.: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1988. Two Treatises of Government. Cambridge, U.K.; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1999. The Reasonableness of Christianity as Delivered in the Scriptures. Edited by John C Higgins-Biddle. Oxford, U.K.: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longinus. 1964. On the Sublime. Edited by D. A. Russell. Oxford, U.K.: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, Ardon. 1976. “The Immutable Laws of Nature.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 77: 107–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey, Elizabeth R. 1985. Niagara Falls: Icon of the American Sublime. Cambridge, U.K.; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabieh, Michael S. 1991. “The Reasonableness of Locke, or the Questionableness of Christianity.” The Journal of Politics 53 (4): 933–957.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1797. Du Contrat Social. Paris: Mourer and Pinparé.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1998. Essay on the Origin of Languages and Writings Related to Music. Edited by John T. Scott. Hanover, NH: University Press of New England.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 2002. The Social Contract ; And, The First and Second Discourses. Edited by Susan Dunn. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, D. A. 1964. “Introduction.” In On the Sublime, by Longinus, i-lv. Oxford, U.K.: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlegel, Dorothy B. 1956. Shaftesbury and the French Deists. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, Marcel. 1978. Jean-Jacques Rousseau et lEspoir Écologiste. Paris: Editions Pygmalion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, John T. 1992. “The Theodicy of the Second Discourse: The ‘Pure State of Nature’ and Rousseau’s Political Thought.” The American Political Science Review 86 (3): 696–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaftesbury, Anthony Ashley Cooper. 1999. Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times. Edited by Lawrence Eliot Klein. Cambridge, U.K.; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaftesbury Papers. n.d. London. National Archives.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin. 1972. “The Context of Hobbes’s Theory of Political Obligation.” In Hobbes and Rousseau: A Collection of Critical Essays, edited by Maurice Cranston and Richard S. Peters, 109-142. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • State, Stephen A. 1985. “Text and Context: Skinner, Hobbes and Theistic Natural Law.” The Historical Journal 28 (1): 27–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stolnitz, Jerome. 1961. “`Beauty’: Some Stages in the History of an Idea.” Journal of the History of Ideas 22 (2): 185–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Annie Edson. 1902. Over the Falls: Annie Edson Taylors Story of Her Trip.

    Google Scholar 

  • Temmer, Mark J. 1961. “Rousseau and Thoreau.” Yale French Studies 28 (January): 112–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Townsend, Dabney. 1987. “From Shaftesbury to Kant: The Development of the Concept of Aesthetic Experience.” Journal of the History of Ideas 48 (2): 287–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trachtenberg, Alan. 1979. Brooklyn Bridge: Fact and Symbol. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walmsley, Peter. 1995. “Prince Maurice’s Rational Parrot: Civil Discourse in Locke’s Essay.” Eighteenth-Century Studies 28 (4): 413–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, Stephen K. 2002. Edmund Burke: Modernity, Politics and Aesthetics. Lanham, MD; Oxford, U.K.: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollstonecraft, Mary. 1995. A Vindication of the Rights of Men; With, A Vindication of the Rights of Woman, and Hints. Cambridge, U.K.; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xenophon. 1914. Cyropaedia. Translated by Walter Miller. London: William Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yolton, John W. 1958. “Locke on the Law of Nature.” The Philosophical Review 67 (4): 477–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2016 The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lukes, T.J. (2016). Swords and Scabbards: Locke’s Occupation of Shaftesbury and Burke. In: Politics and Beauty in America. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-02090-1_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics