Advertisement

When Actions Feel Alien—an Explanatory Model

  • Timothy Lane
Conference paper

Abstract

It is not necessarily the case that we ever have experiences of self, but human beings do regularly report instances for which self is experienced as absent. That is, there are times when body parts, mental states, or actions are felt to be alien. Here, I sketch an explanatory framework for explaining these alienation experiences, a framework that also attempts to explain the “mental glue” whereby self is bound to body, mind, or action. The framework is a multidimensional model that integrates personal and sub-personal components, psychological and neural processes. I then proceed to show how this model can be applied to explain the action-related passivity experiences of persons suffering from schizophrenia. I argue that a distinctive phenomenological mark of these experiences is that they are vividly felt, unlike ordinary actions (those taken to belong to self), and I seek to explain these heightened sensory experiences from within the proposed framework. I also propose hypotheses concerning such phenomena as thought insertion and anarchic hand syndrome that are motivated by this framework. Finally, I argue that the proposed model and view of self-experiences is consistent with several aspects of and theories of consciousness, especially theories which indicate that consciousness is more likely to be engaged when we are dealing with novelty or error—e.g., when self seems to have gone missing. I conclude by recommending that if we wish to learn about self, we would be well advised to attend closely to those times when it seems absent.

Keywords

Conscious Experience Rubber Hand Illusion Posterior Insula Passivity Experience Intentional Binding 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgments

I express my heartfelt gratitude to Ellie Hua Wang and to Tzu-Wei Hung for their constructive comments on previous versions of this manuscript. For much useful discussion, I am also grateful to the many other participants in Academia Sinica’s International Conference on Language and Action, Taipei, Taiwan (September 17–18, 2013). Funding for this research was, in part, provided by National Science Council of Taiwan research grants, 100-2410-H-038-009-MY3 and 102-2420-H-038-001-MY3.

References

  1. Aboitiz, F., Carrasco, X., Schröter, C., Zaidel, D., Zaidel, E., & Lavados, M. (2003). The alien hand syndrome: Classification of forms reported and discussion of a new condition. Neurological Sciences, 24(4), 252–257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Auvray, M., Myin, E., & Spence, C. (2010). The sensory-discriminative and affective-motivational aspects of pain. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 34(2), 214–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Baars, B. J. (2007). Attention and consciousness. In B. J. Baars & N. M. Gage (Eds.), Cognition, brain, and consciousness, second edition: Introduction to cognitive neuroscience (pp. 225–254). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  4. Baars, B. J., Ramsøy, T. Z., & Laureys, S. (2003). Brain, conscious experience and the observing self. Trends in Neurosciences, 26(12), 671–675.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Barbeau, E., Joubert, S., & Poncet, M. (2004). A single case-study of diagnostic dyspraxia. Brain and Cognition, 54(3), 215–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bayne, T. (2010). The unity of consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Bayne, T. (2011). The sense of agency. In F. Macpherson (Ed.), The senses: Classic and contemporary philosophical perspectives (pp. 355–374). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Berthier, M., Starkstein, S., & Leiguarda, R. (1988). Asymbolia for pain: A sensory-limbic disconnection syndrome. Annals of Neurology, 24, 41–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Blakemore, S.-J., Frith, C. D., & Wolpert, D. M. (1999). Spatio-temporal prediction modulates the perception of self-produced stimuli. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 11(5), 551–559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Blakemore, S.-J., Frith, C. D., & Wolpert, D. M. (2000a). Why can’t you tickle yourself? NeuroReport, 11, R11–R16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Blakemore, S.-J., Smith, J., Steel, R., Johnstone, E., & Frith, C. (2000b). The perception of self-produced sensory stimuli in patients with auditory hallucinations and passivity experiences: Evidence for a breakdown of self-monitoring. Psychological Medicine, 30(5), 1131–1139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Bor, D. (2012). The ravenous brain: How the new science of consciousness explains our insatiable search for meaning. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  13. Bortolotti, L. (2010). Delusions and other irrational beliefs. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Cahill, C., & Frith, C. (1996). False perceptions or false beliefs? Hallucinations and delusions in schizophrenia. In P. W. Halligan & J. C. Marshall (Eds.), Method in madness: Case studies in cognitive neuropsychiatry (pp. 267–291). New York: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
  15. Carruthers, P. (2000). Phenomenal consciousness: A naturalistic theory. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Churchland, P. S. (2002). Brain-wise: Studies in neurophilosophy. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  17. Clark, A., Anderson, M. L., Block, N., Bowman, H., Bridgeman, B., Buckingham, G., et al. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(3), 181–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Craig, A. D. (2009). How do you feel—now? The anterior insula and human awareness. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 10(1), 59–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Crick, F., & Koch, C. (2003). A framework for consciousness. Nature Neuroscience, 6(2), 119–126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. David, A. S. (2004). The cognitive neuropsychiatry of auditory verbal hallucinations: An overview. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 9(1/2), 107–123.Google Scholar
  21. Davies, M. (2000). Interaction without reduction: The relationship between personal and sub-personal levels of description. Mind & Society, 1(2), 87–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. de Pinedo-Garcia, M., & Noble, J. (2008). Beyond persons: Extending the personal/subpersonal distinction to non-rational animals and artificial agents. Biology and Philosophy, 23(1), 87–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Edelman, G. M., Gally, J. A., & Baars, B. J. (2011). Biology of consciousness. Frontiers in Psychology, 2, 1–7.Google Scholar
  24. Ellis, H. D., & Lewis, M. B. (2001). Capgras delusion: A window on face recognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5(4), 149–156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Feinberg, T. E. (2009). From axons to identity: Neurological explorations of the nature of the self. New York: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
  26. Fitzgibbon, B. M., Giummarra, M. J., Georgiou-Karistianis, N., Enticott, P. G., & Bradshaw, J. L. (2010). Shared pain: From empathy to synaesthesia. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 34(4), 500–512.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Frith, C. (2005). The self in action: Lessons from delusions of control. Consciousness and Cognition, 14(4), 752–770.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Frith, C. D., Blakemore, S.-J., & Wolpert, D. M. (2000). Explaining the symptoms of schizophrenia: Abnormalities in the awareness of action. Brain Research Reviews, 31(2/3), 357–363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Friston, K. (2009). The free-energy principle: A rough guide to the brain? Trends in Cognitive Science, 13(7), 293–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Gallagher, S. (2012). First-person perspective and immunity to error through misidentification. In S. Miguens & G. Preyer (Eds.), Consciousness and subjectivity (pp. 187–214). Heusenstamm: Ontos.Google Scholar
  31. Grahek, N. (2007). Feeling pain and being in pain (2nd ed.). Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  32. Gray, J. (2004). Consciousness: Creeping up on the hard problem. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Haggard, P., Clark, S., & Kalogeras, J. (2002). Voluntary action and conscious awareness. Nature Neuroscience, 5(4), 382–385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
  35. Hirjack, D., & Fuchs, T. (2010). Delusions of technical alien control: A phenomenological description of three cases. Psychopathology, 43(2), 96–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Jones, E. G. (2007). The thalamus (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Klein, S. B. (2013a). The two selves: Their metaphysical commitments and functional independence. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Klein, S. B. (2013b). Making the case that episodic recollection is attributable to operations occurring at retrieval rather than to content stored in a dedicated subsystem of long-term memory. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 7(3), 1–14. doi:10.3389/fnbeh.2013.00003.Google Scholar
  40. Klein, S. B., & Nichols, S. (2012). Memory and the sense of personal identity. Mind, 121(483), 677–702.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Koch, C. (2004). The quest for consciousness: A neurobiological approach. Englewood: Roberts and Company.Google Scholar
  42. Kühn, S., Brass, M., & Haggard, P. (2013). Feeling in control: Neural correlates of experience of agency. Cortex, 49(7), 1935–1942.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Lane, T. (2012). Toward an explanatory framework for mental ownership. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11(2), 251–286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Lane, T., & Liang, C. (2008). Higher-order thought and the problem of radical confabulation. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 46(1), 69–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Lane, T., & Liang, C. (2010). Mental ownership and higher-order thought. Analysis, 70(3), 496–501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Lane, T., & Liang, C. (2011). Self-consciousness and immunity. Journal of Philosophy, 108(2), 78–99.Google Scholar
  47. Lane, T., & Northoff, G. (2012, July). Mineness, Minimal Self, and Self-Related Processing. Paper presented at the 16th Annual Meeting of the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness. Brighton, UK.Google Scholar
  48. Lane, T., Yeh, S., & Chang, A. (2013, July). Switching Attention to the Rubber Hand. Paper presented at the 17th Annual Meeting of the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness, San Diego, CA.Google Scholar
  49. Lau, H., & Rosenthal, D. (2011). Empirical support for higher-order theories of conscious awareness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(8), 365–373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Marcel, A. (2003). The sense of agency: Awareness and ownership of action. In J. Roessler & N. Eilan (Eds.), Agency and self-awareness: Issues in philosophy and psychology (pp. 48–93). Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  51. Martin, J.-R., & Pacherie, E. (2013). Out of nowhere: Thought insertion, ownership and context-integration. Consciousness and Cognition, 22(1), 111–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  53. Mellor, C. S. (1970). First-rank symptoms of schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 117(536), 15–23.Google Scholar
  54. Metzinger, T. (2003). Being no one: The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  55. Miller, M. B., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Young, L., King, D., Paggi, A., Fabri, M., et al. (2010). Abnormal moral reasoning in complete and partial callosotomy patients. Neuropsychologia, 48(7), 2215–2220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Moore, J. W., & Obhi, S. S. (2012). Intentional binding and the sense of agency: A review. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(1), 546–561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Moore, J. W., Teufel, C., Subramaniam, N., Davis, G., & Fletcher, P. C. (2013). Attribution of intentional causation influences the perception of observed movements: Behavioral evidence and neural correlates. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 23. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00023.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Mullins, S., & Spence, S. A. (2003). Re-examining thought insertion: Semi-structured literature review and conceptual analysis. British Journal of Psychiatry, 182, 293–298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Nordgaard, J., Arnfred, S. M., Handest, P., & Parnas, J. (2008). The diagnostic status of first rank symptoms. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 34(1), 137–154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Northoff, G. (2013a). Unlocking the brain: Vol. 2. Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Northoff, G. (2013b). Unlocking the brain: Vol. 1. Coding. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  62. Northoff, G., & Bermpohl, F. (2004). Cortical midline structures and the self. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(3), 102–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Northoff, G., & Panksepp, J. (2008). The trans-species concept of self and the subcortical-cortical midline system. Trends in Cognitive Science, 12(7), 259–264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Northoff, G., & Qin, P. (2011). How can the brain’s resting state activity generate hallucinations? A “resting state hypothesis” of auditory verbal hallucinations. Schizophrenia Research, 127, 202–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Northoff, G., Lane, T., & Yen, N. (2014). Pre-stimulus neural activity predicts self-relatedness judgments in healthy subjects: A multi-modal study. Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
  66. Pacherie, E. (2011). Self-agency. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 442–464). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  67. Pawar, A. V., & Spence, S. A. (2003). Defining thought broadcast: Semi-structured literature review. British Journal of Psychiatry, 183, 287–291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Prinz, J. (2012a). Waiting for the self. In J.-L. Liu & J. Perry (Eds.), Consciousness and the Self: New essays (pp. 123–149). New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  69. Prinz, J. (2012b). The conscious brain: How attention engenders experience. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Obhi, S. S., & Hall, P. (2011). Sense of agency and intentional binding in joint action. Experimental Brain Research, 211(3/4), 655–662.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Ochsner, K. N., Zaki, J., Hanelin, J., Ludlow, D. H., Knierim, K., Ramachanran, T., et al. (2008). Your pain or mine? Common and distinct neural systems supporting the perception of pain in self and other. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 3(2), 144–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Qin, P., & Northoff, G. (2011). How is our self related to midline regions and the default-mode network? NeuroImage, 57(3), 1221–1233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. Raichle, M. E. (2010). Two views of brain function. Trends in Cognitive Science, 14(4), 180–190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Rosenthal, D. M. (2002). Explaining consciousness. In D. J. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 406–421). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  75. Rosenthal, D. M. (2005). Consciousness and mind. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  76. Rosenthal, D. M. (2008). Consciousness and its function. Neuropsychologia, 46(3), 829–840.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Sass, L. A., & Parnas, J. (2003). Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 29(3), 427–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Schooler, J. W., Smallwood, J., Christoff, K., Handy, T. C., Reichle, E. D., & Sayette, M. A. (2011). Meta-awareness, perceptual decoupling and the wandering mind. Trends in Cognitive Science, 15(7), 319–326.Google Scholar
  79. Seth, A. K., Suzuki, K., & Critchley, H. D. (2012). An interoceptive predictive coding model of conscious presence. Frontiers in Psychology, 2, 395.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  80. Shea, N. (2013). Neural mechanisms of decision-making and the personal level. In K. W. M. Fulford, M. Davies, R. G. T. Gipps, G. Graham, J. Z. Sadler & G. Stanghellini (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy and psychiatry (pp. 1063–1082). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  81. Shoemaker, S. (1994). Self-knowledge and “inner Sense”: Lecture I: The object perception model. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54(2), 249–269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. Sierra, M. (2009). Depersonalization: A new look at a neglected syndrome. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  83. Sorensen, R. (2007). The vanishing point: A model of the self as an absence. Monist, 90(3), 432–456.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. Sperduti, M., Pieron, M., Leboyer, M., & Zalla, T. (2013, July 24). Altered pre-reflective sense of agency in autism spectrum disorders as revealed by reduced intentional binding. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 44(2), 343–352. doi:10.1007/s10803–013-1891-y. (http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10803–013-1891-y.)Google Scholar
  85. Stephens, G. L., & Graham, G. (2000). When self-consciousness breaks: Alien voices and inserted thoughts. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  86. Stone, J. L., & Goodrich, J. T. (2006). The craniopagus malformation: Classification and implications for surgical separation. Brain, 129(5), 1084–1095.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  87. Swiney, L., & Sousa, P. (2013). When our thoughts are not our own: Investigating agency misattribution using the Mind-to-Mind paradigm. Consciousness and Cognition, 22(2), 589–602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  88. Tsakiris, M., Schütz-Bosbach, S., & Gallagher, S. (2007). On agency and body-ownership: Phenomenological and neurocognitive reflections. Consciousness and Cognition, 16(3), 645–660.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  89. Uddin, L. Q. (2011). Brain connectivity and the self: The case of cerebral disconnection. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(1), 94–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  90. Verleger, R., Binkofski, F., Friedrich, M., Sedlmeier, P., & Kömpf, D. (2011). Anarchic-hand syndrome: ERP reflections of lost control over the right hemisphere. Brain and Cognition, 77(1), 138–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  91. Voss, M., Moore, J., Hauser, M., Gallinat, J., Heinz, A., & Haggard, P. (2010). Altered awareness of action in schizophrenia: A specific deficit in predicting action consequences. Brain, 133(10), 3104–3112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  92. Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  93. Wohlschläger, A., Haggard, P., Gesierich, B., & Prinz, W. (2003). The perceived onset time of self-and other-generated actions. Psychological Science, 14(6), 586–591.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  94. Zahn, R., Talazko, J., & Ebert, D. (2008). Loss of the sense of self-ownership for perceptions of objects in a case of right inferior temporal, parieto-occipital and precentral hypometabolism. Psychopathology, 41(6), 397–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  95. Zihl, J., von Cramon, D., & Mai, N. (1983). Selective disturbance of movement vision after bilateral brain damage. Brain, 106(2), 313–340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Singapore 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Graduate Institute of Humanities in MedicineTaipei Medical UniversityTaipeiTaiwan

Personalised recommendations