Skip to main content

Indefinites in Action

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Communicative Action
  • 396 Accesses

Abstract

Karen Lewis (Philos Stud, 158:313–342, 2012) argues that recognizing the importance of plans helps settle a debate regarding the semantics and pragmatics of indefinites. More specifically, Lewis argues against the dynamic approach (e.g., Kamp (In Groenendijk et al., Formal Methods in the Study of Language, pp. 277–322, Mathematics Center, Amsterdam, 1981), Heim (The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases, University of Massachusetts at Amherst, 1982), Groenendijk and Stokhof (Linguist Philos, 14:39–100, 1991), Kamp and Reyle (From Discourse to Logic, Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1993), and Asher and Lascarides (Logics of Conversation, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2003)), according to which indefinite expressions are subject to a semantic Novelty condition. Drawing on data of the so-called summary uses, she claims that Novelty is best analyzed as a pragmatic, cancelable implicature. This chapter throws significant doubt on Lewis’ analysis. Not only is her objection in large part a misreading of dynamic semantics, but the proposed pragmatic account offers no real explanation of even the alleged counterexamples. Once we consider a wider range of linguistic phenomena involving indefinites, the verdict is on the side of the dynamic approach.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The following examples are from Lewis (2012) examples (6)–(9) on p. 318.

  2. 2.

    Gundel et al. (1993, p. 296), example (49).

  3. 3.

    The “antecedent” of the indefinites may be an indefinite (as in (3) and (7)), a proper name (as in (13)), a demonstrative (as in (5)), or a definite (as in (6)).

  4. 4.

    “[A] complete plan for a typical conversation is not decided upon beforehand, but the sort of plans we will be concerned with are speakers’ short-term plans, which we can call local plans” (Lewis 2012, p. 323).

  5. 5.

    The quotes are from Heim (1983, pp. 166, 168), respectively.

  6. 6.

    Heim (1983, p. 165).

  7. 7.

    Lewis (2012, p. 316).

  8. 8.

    Here is another way to block Lewis’ argument. Consider a scenario where whenever a student needed Sue’s help, he did not go to her but asked one of his classmates instead. In this case, the second occurrence of “a student” is still a summary use in the relevant sense, yet it no longer denotes “one and the same student” as the first occurrence of the indefinite noun phrase, i.e., the student that walked into Sue’s office. Of course, such possibility is disastrous for Lewis’ account, but provides further evidence that favors the dynamic analysis. I am grateful to Josh Dever for drawing my attention to this possibility.

  9. 9.

    Earlier dynamic theories, e.g., Kamp (1981); Heim (1982); and Kamp and Reyle (1993), only predict the ambiguity of (10) and strictly speaking do not fully explain (11). But more recent DRT-based theories, such as Asher and Lascarides’ Segmented Discourse Representation Theory (SDRT), do account for the semantic contributions of discourse particles. Very roughly, discourse particles signal the rhetorical structures, e.g., elaboration, consequence, contrast, explanation, etc., so that the discourse relations place more constraints on the accessibility conditions in the DRT-style model theory. Since the primary aim of this chapter is to demonstrate that Lewis’ objections to the dynamic approach are misguided, I will not discuss the full details of a complete explanation of (11) along the lines of SDRT.

  10. 10.

    The recognition of local plans allows “the participants to track the discourse, i.e., know what to expect will likely be a topic of conversation, an object under discussion, or a question being addressed” (Lewis 2012, p. 329).

  11. 11.

    It seems to me that if (16) is to make sense at all, the discourse as a whole means something quite different from (14). The speaker must assume her addressee to have a much stronger degree of familiarity with the said individual.

  12. 12.

    Lewis (2012, p. 318).

  13. 13.

    An interesting twist of the data is the appositional phrases:

    (1) a. A student1 walked into Sue’s office and asked her about his exam.

    b. Finally, a student2, one3 who walked into Sue’s office and asked her about his exam, needed her help!

    Two things to note about the use of appositives. First, suppose the second occurrence of “a student”—a student2—does trigger a general, category-like discourse referent, the appositional phrase—a student3—seems to be about something more specific, i.e., it is about a particular instance of a certain kind. One idea is that in its summary use, an indefinite is to be read into an appositive structure such that the general, purely existential meaning and the identity meaning are both captured.

    One may wonder if, without the presence of the discourse particle “finally,” the appositional phrase alone suffices the indefinite be read in the “summary” sense. That is,

    (2) a. A student1 walked into Sue’s office and asked her about his exam.

    b. A student2, one3 who walked into Sue’s office and asked her about his exam, needed her help!

    I think the answer is negative. It seems to me that somehow the general meaning of “a student” just is not available in discourse (2).

    On the other hand, swapping the two noun phrases in the second sentence results in significant change of meaning:

    (3) a. A student1 walked into Sue’s office and asked her about his exam.

    b. Finally, one3 who walked into Sue’s office and asked her about his exam, a student2, needed her help!

    Discourse (3) sounds much worse, if intelligible at all, and a purely existential, general meaning of a student2 is missing.

    While these phenomena raise an interesting question of the ways “finally” interacts with noun phrases (as they are placed in different parts of the speech) that affect the availability of “summary reading,” it goes far beyond the scope of this chapter to present a full theory of all the relevant details.

  14. 14.

    The intended reading here is not one where “a woman” receives a wide-scope, de re interpretation.

  15. 15.

    Such phenomenon is referred to as modal subordination in the literature. See, for example, Roberts (1987, 1989), Frank and Kamp (1997), and Asher and Pogodalla (2010).

  16. 16.

    See, for example, Asher and Lascarides (2003) and Beaver et al. (2010).

References

  • Anette, F., & Kamp. H. (1997). On context dependence in modal constructions. In A. Lawson (Ed.), Proceedings of SALT VII (pp. 151–168). Ithaca: Cornell University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Lascarides, A. (2003). Logics of conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Pogodalla, S. (2010). A Montagovian treatment of modal subordination. In N. Li & D. Lutz (Eds.), Proceedings of semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) 20 (pp. 387–405). Ithaca: CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaver, D. I., Roberts, C., Simons, M., & Tonhauser, J. (2010). What projects and why. In N. Li & D. Lutz (Eds.), Proceedings of semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) 20 (pp. 309–327). Ithaca: CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (1984). Two faces of intention. The Philosophical Review, 93(3), 375–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., & M. Stokhof. (1991). Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14, 39–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gundel, J., Hedberg, N., & Zacharski, R. (1993). Cognitive status and the form of referring expressions in discourse. Language, 69(2), 274–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1983). File change semantics and the familiarity theory of definiteness. In P. Portner & B. H. Partee (Eds.), Formal semantics: The essential readings (pp. 164–189). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In J. Groenendijk et al. (Eds.), Formal methods in the study of language (pp. 277–322). Amsterdam: Mathematics Center.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From discourse to logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, K. (2012). Discourse dynamics, pragmatics, and indefinites. Philosophical Studies, 158, 313–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollack, M. E. (1992). The use of plans. Artificial Intelligence, 57(1), 43–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, C. (1987). Modal subordination, anaphora, and distributivity. Doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, C. (1989). Modal subordination and pronominal anaphora in discourse. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12, 683–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14, 479–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The chapter benefits greatly from discussions with Josh Dever, Ray Buchanan, and Hans Kamp. I am also thankful for the very helpful comments from Kiki Linton Wang, as well as feedback from the audience at the IEAS conference on Language and Action. The usual disclaimer applies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hsiang-Yun Chen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Singapore

About this paper

Cite this paper

Chen, HY. (2014). Indefinites in Action. In: Hung, TW. (eds) Communicative Action. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-4585-84-2_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics