Skip to main content

Justifying Privacy: The Indian Supreme Court’s Comparative Analysis

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Indian Yearbook of Comparative Law 2018

Part of the book series: The Indian Yearbook of Comparative Law ((IYCL))

  • 260 Accesses

Abstract

The opinion authored by Justice Chandrachud in K. S. Puttaswamy v. Union of India has extensively employed philosophical and comparative materials in justifying a fundamental right to privacy under the Constitution of India. Here, we examine some implications of the reliance on such materials. We first argue that the court relies on a strong liberty-based zonal view of privacy. However, its reliance on Aristotle’s views is controversial, and reliance on JS Mill’s views does not immediately yield a strong zonal argument. The opinion’s aggregation of “intimacy-based”, “expectation-based”, and “other guarantees-based” justifications that are reflected in decisions in the USA also presents conceptual difficulties in understanding the composition of a private zone. We then point out that as in the USA and South Africa, liberty-based justifications in the opinion gradually gravitate towards autonomy-, personhood- and finally, dignity-based accounts. The opinion’s theoretical explanation of the relationship between these concepts however makes their individual content elusive and warrants ironing out of some inconsistencies that emerge. Dignity-based views may not yield a zonal argument like the liberty-based views employed by the opinion earlier. We then indicate that dignity-based arguments for privacy do have to contend with certain differences with liberty-based views owing to their distinct historical evolution in law, and in light of the liberty-restraining potential of dignity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    M. P. Sharma v. Satish Chandra, (1954) SCR 1077.

  2. 2.

    Kharak Singh v. State of UP, (1964) 1 SCR 332.

  3. 3.

    Subbarao J, Ibid., at Para 28.

  4. 4.

    (1978) 1 SCC 248.

  5. 5.

    (2017) 10 SCC 1.

  6. 6.

    See Hart 1963.

  7. 7.

    Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438 (1928).

  8. 8.

    Thomson 1975. For replies, see Rachels 1975, Scanlon 1975.

  9. 9.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 2.

  10. 10.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 29.

  11. 11.

    James 2013.

  12. 12.

    aristotle, politica, book i, in McKeon 2001. See Chaps. 3–13 for a discussion of the household, which is the description of the private sphere.

  13. 13.

    See Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 140(d).

  14. 14.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 168 (emphasis supplied).

  15. 15.

    Ibid.

  16. 16.

    John Stuart Mill, On Liberty and Other Essays (Stefan Collini ed., 1989) (1859) Chs. III and IV.

  17. 17.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 169.

  18. 18.

    See Thomson, supra note 8.

  19. 19.

    See below the discussion of the cases in the USA.

  20. 20.

    Privacy, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2002), available at https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/privacy/.

  21. 21.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 140(c).

  22. 22.

    Supra note 17.

  23. 23.

    Supra note 14.

  24. 24.

    The sceptic would of course be contested by those who argue that privacy is valuable because it protects our control over information about us which is material to how we want to represent ourselves in our social relationships. See Thomson, supra note 8; Marmor 2015.

  25. 25.

    See Part K of the opinion for a survey of US judicial decisions.

  26. 26.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 134(ii).

  27. 27.

    Ibid.

  28. 28.

    Ibid.

  29. 29.

    Wacks 2010.

  30. 30.

    Warren and Brandeis 1890.

  31. 31.

    277 U.S. 438 (1928).

  32. 32.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 158.

  33. 33.

    Post 2001.

  34. 34.

    389 U.S. 347 (1967).

  35. 35.

    Bhatia 2014.

  36. 36.

    Supra note 34 at 2B.

  37. 37.

    Levin and Nicholson 2005 (For the identical conclusion that privacy protection in the USA is a liberty protection).

  38. 38.

    United States v. Jones 565 U.S. 400 (2012) (For an argument based on intimacy); Kyllo v. United States 53 U.S. 27 (2001) (for an intimacy-based argument); Carey 2q2v. Population Services International 431 U.S. 678 (1977) (for an intimacy-based choice argument); Florida v. Jardines 569 U.S. 1 (2013) (for reliance on the idea of an expectation); the dissents in Minnesota v. Olson 495 U.S. 91 (1990) (for an expectation-based argument); Smith v. Maryland 442 U.S. 735 (1979) (expectation-based argument); State v. Miller 425 U.S. 435 (1976) (expectation-based argument).

  39. 39.

    381 U.S. 479 (1965).

  40. 40.

    Ibid., at 10.

  41. 41.

    See Henry 2011 (for an argument of how the varied use of dignity by US courts can be understood not in terms of an essential meaning of dignity through a pluralistic approach typified by Wittgenstein’s idea of family resemblances).

  42. 42.

    410 U.S. 113 (1973).

  43. 43.

    Ibid., at 152.

  44. 44.

    539 U.S. 558 (2003).

  45. 45.

    Ibid., at 1.

  46. 46.

    Supra note 44 at 13.

  47. 47.

    For a discussion of the nature of this connection in the decision, see Baruah 2009.

  48. 48.

    See Baruah 2014.

  49. 49.

    See McCrudden 2008.

  50. 50.

    Ibid. See Waldron (2013). Gallie 1955.

  51. 51.

    Supra note 49 at 722.

  52. 52.

    Dworkin 2010.

  53. 53.

    Supra note 41 at 177.

  54. 54.

    McCrudden, supra note 49 (for a discussion on the varied use of dignity); Rao 2008, Feldman 2000 (providing an analysis of the many ways in which dignity has been used in English law, yet expressing scepticism about its use); O’Mahony 2012, White 2012, Pinker 2008, Bagaric and Allan 2006, Macklin 2003, Brownsword 2003.

  55. 55.

    Pritam Baruah, Human Dignity in Indian Constitutional Adjudication (unpublished manuscript) (on file with authors).

  56. 56.

    Ibid.

  57. 57.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 96.

  58. 58.

    (1981) 1 SCC 608.

  59. 59.

    Baxi 2014).

  60. 60.

    Kamil 2017.

  61. 61.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 107.

  62. 62.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 3(E) [Conclusion]. Indeed such a link between dignity and privacy was proposed in some of the earliest scholarly debates on privacy. See Bloustein 1964.

  63. 63.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 169.

  64. 64.

    See Upper Caste Men Attack Dalit Groom for Riding Horse in Rajasthan, (The Wire, April 30, 2018), https://thewire.in/caste/upper-caste-men-attack-dalit-groom-for-riding-horse-in-rajasthan.

  65. 65.

    See Raz 1991 (for an argument for why the right is a public good).

  66. 66.

    In fact, one of the authors here holds the view that the courts must provide the best reasons available to them in any decision. See Pritam Baruah, supra note 48, Part III.

  67. 67.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 113.

  68. 68.

    Ibid.

  69. 69.

    See Raz 1988.

  70. 70.

    In Germany Article 13 specifically refers to the “inviolability of home”, while the South African Constitution expressly provides for the right to privacy in Section 14: “Everyone has the right to privacy, which includes the right not to have—(a) their person or home searched; (b) their property searched; (c) their possessions seized; or (d) the privacy of their communications infringed.”

  71. 71.

    Chandrachud J, supra note 5 at Para 168.

  72. 72.

    Microcensus 27 BVerfGE 1 (1969).

  73. 73.

    1996 (2) SA 751 (CC).

  74. 74.

    2001 (1) SA 545 (CC).

  75. 75.

    Ibid., at 18.

  76. 76.

    1999 (1) SA 6 (CC).

  77. 77.

    Ibid., at Para 116, quoting, Brennan 1988, quoting Cardozo 1928.

  78. 78.

    Whitman 2004.

  79. 79.

    For a discussion of such views and whether they are continuous with Kantian views, see Whitman 2003 at 243 (arguing that there is such a continuity); for a contrasting view, see Neuman 2003.

  80. 80.

    Waldron and Dan-Cohen 2012; see also Valentini 2017 (for a relational account).

  81. 81.

    Kommers 1997.

  82. 82.

    ERSA Case C-347/03 [2005] ECR I-3785.

  83. 83.

    McAllister 2004.

  84. 84.

    Uzun v. Germany, App no 35623/05, IHRL 1838 (ECHR 2010).

  85. 85.

    See also McCrudden, supra note 49 at 704–705. (for the view that dignity has often been another hurdle to cross for litigants in establishing rights violation).

  86. 86.

    See Whitman, On Nazi “Honour”, supra note 79. Also see, Riley 2010.

  87. 87.

    See Whitman, supra note 78.

  88. 88.

    Whitman, supra note 78 (for how European countries including Germany have restrained the press from disseminating information that did not appear to exhibit an expectation of privacy when the information was made available to others).

  89. 89.

    Manuel Wackenheim v. France Communication No 854/1999, U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/75/D/854/1999 (2002) (report of the UN Human Rights Committee).

References

  • Bagaric, M., & Allan, J. (2006). The vacuous concept of dignity. Journal of Human Rights, 5(2), 257–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baruah, P. (2009). Logic and coherence in Naz Foundation: The arguments of non-discrimination, privacy and dignity. NUJS Law Review, 3, 505–524.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baruah, P. (2014). Human dignity in adjudication: The limits of placeholding and essential contestability accounts. Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence, 27, 329–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baxi, U. (2014). The place of dignity in the Indian constitution. In: M. Düwell, J. Braarvig, R. Brownsword, D. Mieth (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of human dignity. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhatia, G. (2014). State surveillance and the right to privacy in India: A constitutional biography. National Law School of India Review, 26, 127, 130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloustein, E. J. (1964). Privacy as an aspect of human dignity: An answer to Dean Prosser. New York University Law Review, 39, 962.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, W. J. (1988). Reason, passion, and the progress of the law. The forty-second Annual Benjamin N. Cardozo lecture. Cardozo Law Review, 10(3), 10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brownsword, R. (2003). Bioethics today, bioethics tomorrow: Stem cell research and the ‘‘dignitarian alliance’’. Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy, 17(1), 15–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cardozo, B. (1928). The paradoxes of legal science (Vol. 118). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2010). Justice for Hedgehogs (p. 204). Cambridge Mass: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, D. (2000). Human dignity as a legal value: Part 2. Public Law, 61–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallie, W. B. (1955). Essentially contested concepts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56(1), 167–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1963). Law, liberty and morality (Chap. 2). Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, L. M. (2011). The jurisprudence of dignity. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 160, 169, 186.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, M. C. (2013). A comparative analysis of the right to privacy in the United States, Canada and Europe. Connecticut Journal of International Law, 29, 257, 261–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamil, M. (2017). Puttaswamy: Jury still out on some privacy concerns? Indian Law Review, 1(2), 190, 193–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kommers, D. P. (1997). The constitutional jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany 358–360. Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, A., & Nicholson, M. J. (2005). Privacy law in the United States, the EU and Canada: The allure of the middle ground. University of Ottawa Law & Technology Journal, 2(2), 357, 388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macklin, R. (2003). Dignity is a useless concept: It means no more than respect for persons or their autonomy. British Medical Journal, 327, 1419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. (2015). What is the right to privacy? Philosophy and Public Affairs, 43, 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAllister, M. C. (2004). Human dignity and individual liberty in Germany and the United States as examined through each country’s leading abortion cases. Tulsa Journal of Comparative & International Law, 11, 491, 499.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCrudden, C. (2008). Human dignity and judicial interpretation of human rights. European Journal of international Law, 19(4), 655–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKeon, R. (Ed.). (2001). The basic works of Aristotle. New York: Modern Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neuman, G. L. (2003). On fascist honour and human dignity: A sceptical response. In: C. Joerges & N. S. Ghaleigh (Eds.), Darker legacies of law in Europe: The shadow of national socialism and fascism over Europe. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Mahony, C. (2012). There is no such thing as a right to dignity. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 10(2), 551–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2008). The stupidity of dignity. The New Republic, May 28, 2008. http://www.tnr.com/story_print.html?id=d8731cf4-e87b-4d88-b7e7-f5059cd0bfbd.

  • Post, R. (2001). Three concepts of privacy. Georgetown Law Journal, 89, 2087, 2095.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, J. (1975). Why privacy is important. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 4, 322–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rao, N. (2008). On the use and abuse of human dignity in constitutional law. Columbia Journal of European Law, 14, 201–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1988). The morality of freedom 369–395. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1991). Free expression and personal identification. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 11(3), 303–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riley, S. (2010). Human dignity: Comparative and conceptual debates. International Journal of Law in Context, 6, 117, 119–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. (1975). Thomson on privacy. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 4, 315–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1975). The right to privacy. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 4, 295–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, L. (2017). Dignity and human rights: A reconceptualisation. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 37(4), 862–885.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wacks, R. (2010). Privacy: A very short introduction (p. 62). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (2013). Is dignity the foundation of human rights. NYU School of Law, Public Law Research Paper No. 12-73 at 1. Available at https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2196074.

  • Waldron, J., & Dan-Cohen, M. (2012). Dignity, rank, and rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, S. D., & Brandeis, L. D. (1890). The right to privacy. Harvard Law Review, 4, 193, 193–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, E. K. (2012). There is no such thing as a right to human dignity: A reply to Conor O’Mahony. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 10(2), 575–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitman, J. Q. (2003). On Nazi “honour” and the new European “dignity”. In C. Joerges & N. S. Ghaleigh (Eds.), Darker legacies of law in Europe: The shadow of National Socialism and fascism over Europe. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitman, J. Q. (2004). The two western cultures of privacy: Dignity versus liberty. Yale Law Journal, 113, 1151–1221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pritam Baruah .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Baruah, P., Deva, Z. (2019). Justifying Privacy: The Indian Supreme Court’s Comparative Analysis. In: Singh, M., Kumar, N. (eds) The Indian Yearbook of Comparative Law 2018. The Indian Yearbook of Comparative Law. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-13-7052-6_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-13-7052-6_8

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-13-7051-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-13-7052-6

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics