Skip to main content

Peaceful Coexistence: Examining Kent’s Relativistic Solution to the Quantum Measurement Problem

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Reality and Measurement in Algebraic Quantum Theory (NWW 2015)

Part of the book series: Springer Proceedings in Mathematics & Statistics ((PROMS,volume 261))

Abstract

Can there be ‘peaceful coexistence’ between quantum theory and special relativity? Thirty years ago, Shimony hoped that isolating the culprit (i.e. the false assumption) in proofs of Bell inequalities as Outcome Independence would secure such peaceful coexistence: or, if not secure it, at least show a way—maybe the best or only way—to secure it. In this paper, I begin by being sceptical of Shimony’s approach, urging that we need a relativistic solution to the quantum measurement problem (Sect. 2). Then I analyse Outcome Independence in Kent’s realist one-world Lorentz-invariant interpretation of quantum theory (Sects. 3 and 4). Then I consider Shimony’s other condition, Parameter Independence, both in Kent’s proposal and more generally, in the light of recent remarkable theorems by Colbeck, Renner and Leegwater (Sect. 5). For both Outcome Independence and Parameter Independence, there is a striking analogy with the situation in pilot-wave theory. Finally, I will suggest that these recent theorems make some kind of peaceful coexistence mandatory for someone who, like Shimony, endorses Parameter Independence.

Dedicated to the memory of Abner Shimony (1928–2015).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For the dynamical reduction programme, cf. e.g. [3] and Pearle’s essay (2009) in honour of Shimony. For Shimony’s advocacy, cf. e.g. his (1990) and (2009a: Sect. 7, (2)). Excellent philosophical discussions include [49, 50, 52].

  2. 2.

    My (2015) is another such effort. But there are several other proposals deserving more attention from philosophers, such as those of [1], and Landsman and co-authors (2013, 2013a, 2017 Chapters 10.1–3, 11.4).

  3. 3.

    As is also well-known, he asked himself this question in print, in the closing paragraph of his ground-breaking first paper on hidden variables: a paper which, due to an editorial oversight at Reviews of Modern Physics, was only published in 1966, i.e. after he had given a ‘Yes’ answer to the question for deterministic hidden variables, in his 1964 proof of a Bell inequality.

  4. 4.

    From a large subsequent literature, let me pick out just: an early collection, [20], Jarrett’s essay [36] in honour of Shimony, Myrvold’s recent (2016) statement of a position similar to Shimony’s—and a more sceptical position of my own (2007: especially Sects. 3.1 and 3.3, pp. 825–832, 846–851).

  5. 5.

    This condition is found in, for example: Bell’s 1971 paper (2004: pp. 36–38), Clauser and Horne ([16]: Eq. (2’), p. 528), and Shimony ([64]: Sect. 2 Eq. (10), and Sect. 4 Eq. (37)). The facts that this condition (i) occurs in both the Bell, and the Clauser and Horne, papers, and (ii) suffices, together with our earlier ‘no conspiracy’ assumption (that \(\rho \) in Eq. 2 is independent of which quantity is measured), for a Bell inquality, were first clarified by Shimony, Horne, Clauser and Bell in a famous 1976 exchange. It is reprinted as [5], and as Chap. 12 of [62].

  6. 6.

    Reference [35] is the most thorough early source for this ‘conjunction’ point. But we should recall van Fraassen’s brief but masterly exposition, which dubs Parameter Independence ‘Hidden Locality’, and Outcome Independence ‘Causality’ (1982: principles IV and III, respectively, p. 31). Incidentally, Shimony himself came to agree that ‘parameter’ was too general a word for ‘distant setting’. His (2009a: Eqs. 8 and 9) replaces the label ‘Parameter Independence’ by ‘Remote Context Independence’, and correspondingly ‘Outcome Independence’ by ‘Remote Outcome Independence’. But I shall stick to using the established labels.

  7. 7.

    Shimony ([64]: Sects. 3–5) surveys experimental aspects. Fine recent discussions of the contents of the various versions of the theorem include [10, 71].

  8. 8.

    Similarly, some authors ([32, 65]) suggested that the moral of OD was that quantum theory exhibited a species of holism or non-separability. Cf. Morganti ([47]: Sect. 2) as an example of the ongoing philosophical discussion. But as the sequel indicates, I concur with Henson ([30]: pp. 1021–1028, Sect. 3.1–3.4) that this moral does not, as Henson puts it, ‘relieve the problem of Bell’s theorem’.

  9. 9.

    This point echoes Bell’s viewpoint, mentioned in Sect. 1. But perhaps one should say, so as to reflect one’s hope of reconciling the quantum with relativity: not ‘coincidence’, but ‘manna from Heaven’.

  10. 10.

    Fine recent versions of ‘instrumentalism’ include Friederich ([23], Chaps. 7–10) and Healey ([29]: Chap. 4, especially Sect. 4.6 pp. 72–74, and Chap. 10, especially Sect. 10.6, pp. 179–183: building on his previous (2012, 2013, 2014)). For ‘many worlds’, [70] is nowadays the locus classicus.

  11. 11.

    As we will see, the spacetime need not be Minkowski: any appropriately causally well-behaved spacetime will do. There is a more substantial constraint, arising from his appeal to a final boundary condition: viz. that there should be a well-defined limit to a sequence of probability distributions, associated with a sequence of successively later and later spacelike hypersurfaces. But as Kent discusses, there is good reason to think this will be satisfied in favoured cosmological models.

  12. 12.

    Remark: Kent’s focus is on the measurement problem, which he prefers to call the reality problem, ‘since few physicists now believe that the fundamental laws of nature involve measuring devices per se or that progress can be made by analysing them’ (2014, 012107–1). Hence the title of his paper. I agree with his preference for ‘reality problem’ over ‘measurement problem’: but I will keep to the traditional term, reflecting his wider concern by talking about seeking an ‘interpretation of quantum theory’.

  13. 13.

    After expounding stages (i)–(iii), Kent discusses taking S ever later in spacetime, i.e. letting S go to future infinity; and therefore his proposal needs the probability distributions associated to ever later S to have an appropriate limit: cf. footnote 11. But I shall not discuss this aspect.

  14. 14.

    Though much could be said about this topic, this is not the place: except for two short points, the first historical and the second conceptual. (1): Though I duly cited d’Espagnat’s clear and influential presentation of the point, and nowadays the decoherence literature often says it clearly (e.g. Zeh, Joos et al. (2003, p. 36, 43); Janssen (2008, Sects. 1.2.2, 3.3.2)), it is humbling to recall that Schrödinger already was clear on it in his amazing 1935 papers: cf. especially the analogy with a school examination (1935, Sect. 13, p. 335 f.). (2): Although I thus condemn this ‘one fell swoop’ solution (joining, of course, much wiser authorities including Bell): I of course agree that the result here—obtaining an improper mixture nearly diagonal in a quantity you ‘want’ to have definite values—can form an important part of a principled, and clear-headed, solution to the measurement problem. The obvious example is the modal interpretation, in its early versions from the mid-1990s (cf. [22]): which, roughly speaking, proposed as a postulate, going beyond quantum theory, that the eigenprojections of any system’s density matrix have definite values.

  15. 15.

    For clarity and simplicity, I will again suppress the need to let the late spacelike hypersurface S go to future infinity. Cf. footnotes 11 and 13.

  16. 16.

    So in terms of the formalism: Kent’s idea is like an appeal to one ‘branch’ of the state of an environmental particle, i.e. one component of its improper mixture, to pick out as factual the corresponding (strictly correlated) component of the improper mixture of the system of interest. But only ‘like’, not ‘identical with’! As I stressed in Sect. 3.2.2’s Contrasts with ‘decoherence as usual’: the difference is that Kent avoids the error of assuming an improper mixture is ignorance-interpretable. He knowingly postulates the beables, and their probabilities, that secure an actual quasiclassical history, while avoiding this error.

  17. 17.

    Again, there is an interesting comparison with the pilot-wave theory. For my question to Kent is the analogue of a question sometimes raised about the pilot-wave theory. Namely: does the ‘psycho-physical parallelism’ ([69], Chap. VI.1 p. 418f.) between some mental states, such as states of perceptual knowledge, and some physical states of our sensory organs (e.g. depression of a touch receptor in my fingertip, or photons impinging on my retina) mean that a perception being definite—one way rather than another—involves a point-particle being in one wave-packet rather than another? (For example, cf. Brown and Wallace (2005: Sect. 7, pp. 533–537).) But I think that on this topic, Kent’s situation is much more comfortable than the pilot-wave theorist’s. For according to modern psychophysics, it is much more plausible that mental states being one way rather than another correspond to (i) values of components of stress-energy at locations in the brain being one way rather another, than to (ii) point-particles being in one location rather than another.

  18. 18.

    There is nothing suspect about such tenseless verbs. They are not a philosophers’ fiction or contrivance: the verbs in proverbs, e.g. ‘a stich in time saves nine’, and in pure mathematics, e.g. ‘1 + 1 \(=\) 2’, are tenseless.

  19. 19.

    Here again, the words ‘registering’, and ‘recording that it reflected’, are to be understood tenselessly, in line with the warning at the end of Sect. 4.1. That is: there is indeed an actual fact as to which reflection happens (tenselessly!). But this fact is not independent of, nor is it ‘made true’ or ‘settled’ before the time of, the actual final condition.

  20. 20.

    This difference implies no criticism of Kent: the pilot-wave theory is long-established, and most expositions of its recovery of orthodoxy do not involve any cosmological, and so inevitably speculative, considerations of the kind Kent’s proposal must tangle with.

  21. 21.

    Furthermore, Leegwater allows the measure over hidden variables to depend on more than just the quantum state (although not which quantity is measured). For example, it can depend on the specific method that was used to prepare the state. I stress that discerning the no-conspiracy assumption is not original to me: Landsman and Leegwater are perfectly clear that they make this assumption, even though it is not given a formal label or acronym ([43], pp. 122103–2, assumption CQ and its footnote 14; 2017, p. 221, Definition 6.20 and following text; [45], p. 21 footnote 7 and its preceding text).

  22. 22.

    Note the obvious contrast with the dynamical reduction programme, i.e. with the view that the universal quantum state evolves non-unitarily, collapsing appropriately throughout history so as to yield a quasiclassical world (cf. footnote 2 and Sect. 5.2). On that view, the quasiclassical world no doubt includes which quantity, or quantities, are measured at all the various times, and so the final universal quantum state certainly will depend on such facts. So in such a universe, a Kentian algorithm applied to the final condition would violate no-conspiracy.

References

  1. Allahverdyan, A., Ballian R. and Nieuwenhuizen T.: Understanding quantum measurement from the solution of dynamical models. Physics Reports 525 1–166 (2013).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  2. Barrett, J.: The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds, Oxford University Press; (1999).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bassi, A. and Ghirardi, G.C.: Dynamical reduction models. Physics Reports 379, 257–426 (2003).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  4. Bell, J: Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, Cambridge: University Press; second edition(2004).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Bell, J. and Shimony, A., Horne, M. and Clauser, J.: An exchange on local beables, Dialectica 39, 85–1110 (1985).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Berndl, K: Global existence and uniqueness of Bohmian trajectories, In Cushing J., Fine A. and Goldstein S. (eds), Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Theory: An Appraisal, Kluwer Academic; arXiv:quant-ph/9509009 (1996).

  7. Berndl, K., Dürr D., Goldstein S., Peruzzi G. and Zanghi, N: On the global existence of Bohmian mechanics, Communications in Mathematical Physics 173, 647–673 (1995).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  8. Bohm, D. and Hiley, B. The Undivided Universe, London: Routledge (1992).

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Bricmont, J.: Making Sense of Quantum Mechanics, Springer (2016).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Brown, H. and Timpson, C.: Bell on Bell’s theorem: the changing face of nonlocality, in M. Bell and Shan Gao (eds), Quantum Nonlocality and Reality: Fifty Years of Bell’s Theorem, Cambridge University Press; arXiv:1501.03521 (2016).

  11. Brown, H. and Wallace D.: Solving the measurement problem: de Broglie-Bohm loses out to Everett, Foundations of Physics 35, 517–540 (2005).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  12. Butterfield, J .: Bell’s Theorem: what it takes, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science43, 41–83 (1992).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. Butterfield, J .: Stochastic Einstein Locality Revisited, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science58, 805–867 (2007).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  14. Butterfield, J .: Assessing the Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics52A, 75–85; At: http://arXiv.org/abs/1406.4351; http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/10761/ (2015).

  15. d’Espagnat. B.: Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Mechanics Reading, Mass: Benjamin; second edition (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Clauser, J. and Horne, M.: Experimental consequences of objective local theories, Physical Review D  10 526–534 (1974).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Clifton, R. and Jones, M.: Against experimental metaphysics. In: French, P., Euling, T. and Wettstein, H. (eds.) Midwest Studies in Philosophy, volume 18: Philosophy of Science; Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press; 295–316 (1993).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Colbeck, R. and Renner, R.: No extension of quantum theory can have improved predictive power, Nature Communications 2, 411. https://doi.org/10.1038/ncomms1416 (2011).

  19. Colbeck, R. and Renner, R.: The completeness of quantum theory for predicting measurement outcomes. arXiv:1208.4123 (2012).

  20. Cushing, J. and McMullin, E. (eds): Philosophical Lessons from Quantum Theory, University of Notre Dame Press (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Dewdney, C., Holland P. and Kyprianidis, A.: A causal account of non-local Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen spin correlations, Journal of Physics A: Math. Gen. 20, 4717–4732 (1987).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  22. Dieks, D and Vermaas, P. (eds.): The Modal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Kluwer (1998).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Friederich, S.: Interpreting Quantum Theory: a Therapeutic Approach, Palgrave Macmillan (2015).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ghirardi, G.: The interpretation of quantum mechanics: where do we stand?, Journal of Physics: Conference Series 174 (DICE 2008) 012013 (2009).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ghirardi, G., Rimini, A. and Weber, T: A general argument against superluminal transmission through the quantum mechanical measurement process, Lettere al Nuovo Cimento 27, 293–298 (1980).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  26. Healey, R: Quantum theory: a pragmatist approach, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 63, 729D771 (2012).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  27. Healey, R: How quantum theory helps us explain, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 64, 1–43; https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axt031 (2013).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  28. Healey, R: Causality and chance in relativistic quantum field theories, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 48, 156–167 (2014).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  29. Healey, R.: The Quantum Revolution in Philosophy, Oxford University Press (2017).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Henson, J.: Non-separability does not relieve the problem of Bell’s theorem, Foundations of Physics  43, 1008–1038 (2013).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  31. Holland, P.: The Quantum Theory of Motion, Cambridge: University Press (1993).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  32. Howard, D.: Holism, separability and the metaphysical implications of the Bell experiments. In: Cushing and McMullin (eds.) (1989), pp. 224–253 (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Isham, C: Lectures on Quantum Theory, London; Imperial College Press (1995).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  34. Janssen, H.: Reconstructing Reality: Environment-Induced Decoherence, the Measurement Problem, and the Emergence of Definiteness in Quantum Mechanics. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/4224/ (2008).

  35. Jarrett, J.: On the physical significance of the locality conditions in the Bell arguments, Nous 18, 569–589 (1984).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  36. Jarrett, J.: On the separability of physical systems, in Myrvold, W. and Christian, J. (eds.) (2009); pp. 105–124 (2009).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Jordan, T.: Quantum correlations do not transmit signals, Physics Letters 94A, 264 (1983).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Kent, A.: Solution to the Lorentzian quantum reality problem, Physical Review A 90, 012107; arXiv:1311.0249 (2014).

  39. Kent, A.: Lorentzian quantum reality: postulates and toy models, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A 373, 20140241; arXiv:1411.2957 (2015).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Kent, A.: Quantum reality via late-time photodetection, Physical Review A 96, 062121; arXiv:1608.04805 (2017).

  41. Landsman, N.: Spontaneous symmetry breaking in quantum systems: emergence or reduction? Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44(4), 379–394 (2013).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  42. Landsman, N. and Reuvers, R: A flea on Schrödinger’s cat. Foundations of Physics 43, 373–407 (2013a).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  43. Landsman, N.: The Colbeck-Renner theorem, Journal of Mathematical Physics 56, 122103 (2015).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  44. Landsman, N.: Foundations of Quantum Theory, Springer (2017). Open access: available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-51777-3

    Book  Google Scholar 

  45. Leegwater, G.: An impossibility theorem for parameter independent hidden variable theories, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics54 18–34; http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/12067/ (2016).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  46. Leggett, A.: Probing Quantum Mechanics Towards the Everyday World: Where do we Stand?, Physica ScriptaT102, 69–73 (2002).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Morganti, M. A new look at relational holism in quantum mechanics, Philosophy of Science76, 1027–1038 (2009).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Muller, F.: The locality scandal of quantum mechanics. In: Dalla Chiara, M. et al. (eds.), Language, Quantum, Music, Synthese Library volume 281, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 241–248 (1999).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  49. Myrvold, W.: On peaceful coexistence: is the collapse postulate incompatible with relativity? Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics33, 435–466 (2002).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  50. Myrvold, W.: Relativistic quantum becoming, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science54, 475–500 (2003).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  51. Myrvold, W.: Lessons of Bell’s theorem: Nonlocality, yes; Action at a distance, not necessarily, in M. Bell and Shan Gao (eds), Quantum Nonlocality and Reality: Fifty Years of Bell’s Theorem, Cambridge University Press. Available at: http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/12382/ (2016).

  52. Myrvold, W.: Ontology for collapse theories, forthcoming in Shan Gao (ed.) Collapse of the Wave Function, Cambridge University Press (2017).

    Google Scholar 

  53. Myrvold, W. and Christian, J. (eds.): Quantum Reality, Relativistic Causality, and Closing the Epistemic Circle: Essays in Honor of Abner Shimony, Springer (2009).

    Google Scholar 

  54. Norsen, T: Local causality and completeness: Bell vs. Jarrett, Foundations of Physics39, 273–294 (2009).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  55. Norsen, T: John S. Bell’s concept of local causality, American Journal of Physics79, 1261–1275 (2011).

    Google Scholar 

  56. Pearle, P.: How stands collapse II, in Myrvold, W. and Christian, J. (eds.) (2009); pp. 257–292 (2009).

    Google Scholar 

  57. Redhead, M: Incompleteness, Nonlocality and Realism Oxford: University Press (1987).

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  58. Schrödinger, E.: The Present Situation in Quantum Mechanics: A Translation of Schrödinger’s ‘Cat Paradox’ Paper (trans: J D. Trimmer) Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society,124, (Oct. 10, 1980), pp. 323–338; American Philosophical Society; http://www.jstor.org/stable/986572 (1935).

  59. Shimony, A.: Controllable and uncontrollable nonlocality. In: Kamefuchi , S. et al. (eds) Foundations of Quantum Mechanics in the Light of New Technology, Tokyo: Physical Society of Japan; reprinted in Shimony (1993), 130–139: page references to reprint (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  60. Shimony, A.: Events and processes in the quantum world. In: Penrose, R. and Isham C. (eds.) Quantum Concepts in Space and Time Oxford: University Press; reprinted in Shimony (1993), 140–162: page references to reprint (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  61. Shimony, A.: Desiderata for a modified quantum dynamics. In: (eds.) PSA 1990 volume 2; Proceedings of the 1990 meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association; East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association; reprinted in Shimony (1993), 55–67 (1990).

    Google Scholar 

  62. Shimony, A.: Search for a Naturalistic World View: Volume II: natural science and metaphysics. Cambridge: University Press (1993).

    Google Scholar 

  63. Shimony, A.: Unfinished work, a bequest. In: Myrvold and Christian (eds.) (2009); pp. 479–491 (2009).

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  64. Shimony, A.: Bell’s theorem, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/bell-theorem/ (2009a).

  65. Teller, P.: Relativity, relational holism and the Bell inequalities. In: Cushing and McMullin (eds.) (1989) pp. 208–223 (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  66. Valentini, A.: Signal locality in hidden variable theories, Physics Letters A297, 273–278; arXiv:quant-ph/0106098 (2002).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  67. Valentini, A.: Signal locality and sub-quantum information in deterministic hidden variable theories, in T. Placek and J. Butterfield (eds.) Non-Locality and Modality NATO Science Series II: volume 64, Kluwer; arXiv:quant-ph/0112151 (2002a).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  68. van Fraassen, B.: The charybdis of realism: epistemological implications of Bell’s theorem, Synthese52; 25–38 (1982).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  69. von Neumann, J.: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton: University Press (English translation 1955, reprinted in the Princeton Landmarks series 1996) (1932).

    Google Scholar 

  70. Wallace, D.: The Emergent Multiverse, Oxford University Press (2012).

    Google Scholar 

  71. Wiseman, H. and Cavalcanti, E.: Causarum Investigatio and the two Bell’s theorems of John Bell, in Quantum Unspeakables II, ed. R. Bertlmann and A. Zeilinger, Springer; pp. 119–142; arXiv:1503.06413 (2017).

  72. Zeh, H-D, Joos, E. et al.; Decoherence and the Appearance of a Classical World in Quantum Theory, second edition; Springer (2003).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Dedicated to the memory of Abner Shimony. As all who met him soon realized, it was a pleasure and a privilege to know him, both as a person and as an intellect. It is a pleasure to thank Masanao Ozawa for the invitation to the Nagoya conference; and to thank him, Francesco Buscemi and the other local organizers, for a very enjoyable and valuable meeting. I am very grateful to Adrian Kent for generous advice and encouragement; and to Bryan Roberts for the splendid diagram. For comments on a previous version, I thank an anonymous referee, audiences in Cambridge, Wayne Myrvold, James Read, Bryan Roberts and four Dutch wizards: Dennis Dieks, Fred Muller and especially Guido Bacciagaluppi and Gijs Leegwater.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeremy Butterfield .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Butterfield, J. (2018). Peaceful Coexistence: Examining Kent’s Relativistic Solution to the Quantum Measurement Problem. In: Ozawa, M., Butterfield, J., Halvorson, H., Rédei, M., Kitajima, Y., Buscemi, F. (eds) Reality and Measurement in Algebraic Quantum Theory. NWW 2015. Springer Proceedings in Mathematics & Statistics, vol 261. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-13-2487-1_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics