Skip to main content

A Role of Doing Philosophy in a Humanistic Approach to Teacher Education

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
A Companion to Research in Teacher Education

Abstract

In teaching a philosophy of education course within teacher training program, we are often challenged by self-assertive student-teachers with questions like: “What is the relevance of philosophy to teacher training?” or more specifically, “What is the relevance of ‘philosophy of education’ to the (professional) life of teachers?” Knowing that any attempt to respond to such questions in the form of justificatory claims—i.e., giving the account of how useful it may be—will sound unconvincing to them, I tend to throw the question back at them, asking what sort of relevance they can conceive of in terms of its preparation for their professional lives.

An earlier version of this essay, “Stanley Cavell’s Ordinary Language Philosophy as an Example of Practicing Philosophy in the Essay-form: In Search of a Humanistic Approach to Teacher Education,” was published in Teachers College Record, 113:8 (2011). I am grateful for permission to use this material here.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    What is assumed here is that practically minded students will be looking for some instrumental connection between philosophy and their professional lives. That is, they will want to know what skills and competences philosophy will equip them with.

  2. 2.

    In his book Exploring the Moral Heart of Teaching (2001), David Hansen refreshingly explores the nature and predicament of teaching that can be well articulated and responded to by the humanistic sensibility.

  3. 3.

    Think, for example, of the kind of classroom setting with students from different ethnic and cultural backgrounds that is seen in the recently released French film, The Class (2009), and the kinds of challenges that these rebellious students present to the teacher. These wild and unconventional, yet curious and self-assertive students seem to represent a new kind of challenge to teachers today. Even in Korea today, well-intentioned young teachers often leave their teaching career after the disillusionment they experience when confronted by wild teenage students, who seem completely unintelligible to them.

  4. 4.

    Emphasizing this modernist aspect of Montaigne’s philosophy, Hartle calls it ‘accidental philosophy’, implying the radically contingent and created order of the world (Hartle 2003, pp. 3–27).

  5. 5.

    The term ‘modern art’ is usually associated with art in which, in a spirit of experimentation, the traditions and conventions of the past are no longer taken for granted, and it refers to artworks produced during the period extending roughly from the 1860s through to the 1970s. Modern artists experimented with new ways of seeing and with fresh ideas about the nature of materials and the functions of art, being highly conscious of the nature of their own practice. A salient characteristic of modern art is self-consciousness. This often led to experiments with form and work that draw attention to the processes and materials used. I think that the same thing can be said about the nature of what Cavell attempts to do in his practice of philosophy.

  6. 6.

    Now it may be objected that this is a slight variation on the formulation of words with which ordinary language philosophy is most commonly associated, which is “When we say…, we mean…” And indeed Cavell makes much of the importance of this being both first person and plural, indicating first that we are required to say how things seem to us, and second that in so doing we are trying to speak for others too, making an appeal to community. But it is this very point that legitimates my expressing this in the second person: in doing ordinary language philosophy with others (and how else could it be done?), I must take the other’s first person expression as at the same time an address to me, to see if this is what I mean by the words I use.

  7. 7.

    Some people are very good at explaining what they mean by their words, putting their thoughts another way, perhaps referring to a range of similar or identical thoughts that have been expressed by others, depending upon who the listeners are. These good explainers are those who are quick to notice what prevents the listeners from understanding the meaning of their words, whether this is their presuppositions, their prejudices and so forth. But to explain what I mean by my words is basically to reproduce the literal meaning of the words; nothing is to be added to the original meaning of them. On the other hand, in the case of metaphor, in giving the paraphrase, we are free to create meaning in an indefinite way. According to Cavell, this is the very attraction of metaphor as a form of expression, even if there is always the danger of over-reading (Cavell 1976, p. 79).

  8. 8.

    Cavell cites as examples of poetic expression of this kind “The mind is brushed by sparrow wings,” and “as a calm darkens among water-light” (Cavell 1976, p. 81).

  9. 9.

    ‘Transcendental argument’ refers to a kind of philosophical inquiry that seeks to spell out all the presuppositions that are necessary to make sense of experience, or all the objective conditions that are necessary to make our experience at all. The first technical distinction between the terms ‘transcendent’ and ‘transcendental’ was made by Kant. Kant reserved the term ‘transcendent’ for entities such as God and soul that are said to be beyond human experience and to be unknowable. The term ‘transcendental’ Kant reserved to signify prior thought forms: the innate principles that give the mind the ability to formulate its perceptions and to make experience intelligible.

  10. 10.

    In A Pitch of Philosophy (1994), Cavell introduces an autobiographical example that shows vividly the way we have an access to the meaning of a work of art. According to Cavell, in his college music class, a famous teacher, Ernest Bloch, often introduced an exercise to the students by playing something simple at the piano, for instance, a Bach four-part chorale, with one note altered by a half step from Bach’s rendering, and then with the Bach unaltered. Introducing these two versions, he asked the students if they could hear the difference. And then he went on to say: “my version is perfectly correct; but the Bach, the Bach is perfect; late sunlight burning the edges of a cloud. Of course, I do not say you must hear this. Not at all. No. But, if you do not hear it, do not say to yourself that you are a musician. There are many honorable trades, Shoe-making for example (Cavell 1994, pp. 49–50). Cavell confesses that he heard the difference, supposing that not everybody did, and describes how thrilled he was by the drama of this teaching because it made him interested in the understanding of what he heard as well as in the rightness and beauty of what he heard. I think that this sense of a private triumph about what we experience is exactly what ordinary language philosophy aspires towards for our education.

  11. 11.

    The recent discourse of ‘emotional intelligence’ or ‘emotional literacy’ in the practice of teaching and learning tends to highlight interpersonal sensitivity and emotional responsiveness not only as an effective pedagogical virtue but also as an educational aim. The term ‘emotional literacy’ was coined and popularized in the 1990’s in the field of positive psychology, especially in the UK, whereas the term ‘emotional intelligence’ became popularized in the US by Daniel Goleman’s book Emotional Intelligence (1995).

References

  • Blumeberg, H. (1983). The legitimacy of the modern age (R. M. Wallace, Trans.). Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, W. (1995). For education: Towards critical educational research. Buckingham: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, W. (2005). Philosophy of education. In W. Carr (Ed.), Philosophy of education. London & New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, W. (2007). Philosophy, methodology, and action research. In D. Bridges & R. Smith (Eds.), Philosophy, methodology and educational research. Oxford: Blackwell Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (1976). Must we mean what we say? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (1988). In quest of the ordinary: Lines of scepticism and romanticism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (1990). Handsome and unhandsome: The constitution of emersonian perfectionism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (1994). A pitch of philosophy. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunne, J. (1993). Back to the rough ground: Practical judgment and the lure of technique. Notre Dame, Indiana: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goleman, D. (1995). Emotional intelligence. New York: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot, P. (1995). (M. Chase, Trans.). In A. I. Davidson (Ed.), Philosophy as a way of life. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, D. (2001). Exploring the moral heart of teaching. New York: Teachers College, Columbia University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartle, A. (2003). Michel de Montaigne: Accidental philosopher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, P. H., & Carr, W. (2005). Philosophy of education—A symposium. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 39(4), 615–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montaigne, M. (1958). The essays (J. M. Cohen, Trans.). London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigation (3rd. G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Duck-Joo Kwak .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kwak, DJ. (2017). A Role of Doing Philosophy in a Humanistic Approach to Teacher Education. In: Peters, M., Cowie, B., Menter, I. (eds) A Companion to Research in Teacher Education. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-4075-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-4075-7_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-10-4073-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-10-4075-7

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics