Skip to main content

Engagement, Expression, and Initiation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
A Companion to Wittgenstein on Education

Abstract

According to what has been called a “Transformational” account of education , a child comes to possess rational and conceptual capacities as a result of initiation into culture or a “form of life.” I consider how we must understand the engagement with other minds involved in education if we are to make sense of the Transformational view. I argue that Wittgenstein’s discussions of perceiving and mimicking other minds provide the resources to respond to worries one might have with the idea that a genuine meeting of minds can occur in education prior to the acquisition of sophisticated capacities for reasoning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Readers of Wittgenstein who attribute the Transformational view to him include McDowell (1994), Williams (1999, 2010), Huemer (2006), Stickney (2008a, b), Smeyers (2008), and Bakhurst (2011). This attribution is challenged by Luntley (2008, 2009). I won’t address the interpretive question here.

  2. 2.

    According to Luntley , a Rationalist , we must “acknowledge that the learner can only respond to training if they already possess sufficient mental equipment to generate the appropriate responses” (Luntley 2008: 695). Luntley (2009) uses the labels “Empiricist” and “Rationalist ” in a similar way.

  3. 3.

    Luntley (2009) and Bakhurst (2011) also frame the question facing the Transformative view in terms of the child’s entrance into the space of reasons.

  4. 4.

    The Transformational view should not be interpreted as holding that all concepts are socially constructed, though. See Bakhurst (2011), Chap. 3 for a helpful discussion.

  5. 5.

    See Bakhurst (2011), Chap. 1 and Williams (1999) for further discussion of this process.

  6. 6.

    It won’t help to insist that, according to its advocates, the analogical and theoretical reasoning involved are implicit. If education is a meeting of minds, then it involves personal level awareness on the part of the pupil . If minds are hidden, as Inferentialists hold, then this awareness must be mediated by inferences.

  7. 7.

    Following convention, titles for Wittgenstein’s works are abbreviated (PI = Philosophical Investigations, BB = The Blue and Brown Book, OC = On Certainty, RPP I = Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology I, RPP II = Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology II, Z = Zettel), with section (§) or page number (p.), with full citation and initials in the References.

  8. 8.

    I do not read Wittgenstein’s harsh use of the word “training ” to commit him to a version of Empiricism , but, as mentioned, I won’t take up the point here.

  9. 9.

    See also PI §244, PI §284, RPP1 §1070, Z §225, Z §472, for a start.

  10. 10.

    The idea that expressions of emotion serve as a commentary on the shared environment is mentioned by Roessler (2006).

  11. 11.

    If this is Wittgenstein’s view, then he must think that the same capacity at play in initiate learning is exercised in our mature knowledge of other minds , which is an intriguing suggestion.

  12. 12.

    The place of primitive , animal reactions in education is emphasized in Stickney (2008a).

  13. 13.

    Thanks to Jeff Stickney for drawing my attention to the relevance of this passage.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (2000). Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakhurst, D. (2011). The formation of reason. London: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. (1997). Words, thoughts, and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, W. (2006). The transition from causes to norms: Wittgenstein on training. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 71, 205–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (1987). Children’s understanding of the mental world. In R. L. Gregory & O. L. Zangwill (Eds.), Oxford companion to the mind. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luntley, M. (2008). Training and learning. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 40(5), 695–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luntley, M. (2009). On the teaching and learning of words. In E. Zamuner & D. K. Levy (Eds.), Wittgenstein’s enduring arguments (pp. 135–155). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V. (2008). How infants know minds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roessler, J. (2006). Joint attention and the problem of other minds. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler (Eds.), Joint attention: Communication and other minds (pp. 230–259). Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (1943/1956). Being and nothingness (H. E. Barnes, Trans.). New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1963). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In Science, perception, and reality (pp. 127–196). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smeyers, P. (2008). Images and pictures: Seeing and imagining. In M. A. Peters, N. Burbules, & P. Smeyers (Eds.), Saying and doing: Wittgenstein as a pedagogical philosopher. Boulder: Paradigm Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stickney, J. (2008a). Wittgenstein’s ‘Relativity’: Training in language games and agreement in forms of life. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 40(5), 621–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stickney, J. (2008b). Training and mastery of techniques in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy: A response to Michael Luntley. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 40(5), 678–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. (1999). Vygotsky’s social theory of mind. Wittgenstein, mind, and meaning (pp. 260–280). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. (2010). Blind obedience. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1972a). Philosophical investigations (3rd ed., R. Rhees & G. E. M. Anscombe Eds., G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell (PI).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1972b). Preliminary studies for the “Philosophical Investigations”, generally known as the blue and brown books (2nd ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell (BB).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). On certainty (G. H. von Wright & G. E. M. Anscombe, Eds., G. E. M. Anscombe & D. Paul, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell (OC).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980a). Remarks on the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 1, G. E. M. Anscombe, G. H. von Wright, & R. Rhees Eds., G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell (RPP I).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980b). Remarks on the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 2, M. Nyman & G. H. von Wright, Eds., C. G. Luckhardt & A. E. Aue, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell (RPP II).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1981). Zettel (G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright, Eds., G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell (Z).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Casey Doyle .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Doyle, C. (2017). Engagement, Expression, and Initiation. In: Peters, M., Stickney, J. (eds) A Companion to Wittgenstein on Education. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-3136-6_31

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-3136-6_31

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-10-3134-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-10-3136-6

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics