Skip to main content

The Weight of Dogmatism: Investigating “Learning” in Dewey’s Pragmatism and Wittgenstein’s Ordinary Language Philosophy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

What is it to learn something? This essay is an attempt to give a treatment of our expectations and wants from an answer to that question by placing Dewey’s pragmatism and Wittgenstein’s ordinary language philosophy in conversation with each other. Both Dewey and Wittgenstein introduce philosophical visions and methods that are meant to avoid dogmatic responses to such questions. Dewey presents a vision of learning based on the view of the human organism transacting in its environment and in that way being involved with education without any other end than continual growth. By suggesting possible results of a Wittgensteinian investigation of our use of the word “learning ”, the essay also proposes a twist on Dewey’s theory of learning, which dissolves our need for a theory of learning as an answer to the question. This gives the child a voice in contexts where the word “learn” is used. An investigation of the use of “learn” becomes a method of releasing us from the dogmatic requirements that determine what learning is. Further, Dewey’s terminology comes to comprise examples of possible uses rather than being a statement as to what learning is.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Following convention, titles for Wittgenstein’s works are abbreviated (PI = Philosophical Investigations , OC = On Certainty, RFM = Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, CV = Culture and Value), with section (§) or page number (p.), with full citation and initials in the References.

  2. 2.

    For a complementary discussion of the educational aspects of this passage, see Stickney (2008).

  3. 3.

    There has been some discussion regarding how to translate Wittgenstein’s “übereinstimmung”. “Agreement” is common, but I follow Cavell’s suggestion in my use of “attunement”. See Cavell (1979: pp. 31–32).

  4. 4.

    See PI §§143–148, 185 and the discussion of rule-following and private language remarks in Johansson (2013, pp. 161–181).

References

  • Biesta, G., & Burbules, N. (2003). Pragmatism and educational research. Oxford: Roman and Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (1979). The claim of reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (1996). Notes and afterthoughts on the opening of Wittgenstein’s investigations. In H. Sluga & D. Stern (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (2002). Must we mean what we say? (2nd updated ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (2003). Emerson’s transcendental etudes. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (2011). Gilles Deleuze from A to Z [DVD]. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1994). What is philosophy? New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1897). Ethical principles underlying education. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), The early works of John Dewey, 1882-1898 (Vol. 5). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1916). Democracy and education. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), The middle works of John Dewey, 1899-1924 (Vol. 9). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1920). Reconstruction in philosophy. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), The middle works of John Dewey, 1899-1924 (Vol. 12). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1925). Experience and nature. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), The later works of John Dewey, 1925-1953 (Vol. 5). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (2012). Unmodern philosophy and modern philosophy. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, C. (1991). The realistic spirit: Wittgenstein, philosophy and the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldridge, R. (1997). Leading a human life: Wittgenstein, intentionality and romanticism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrison, J. (2013). 2012 Dewey lecture: Making meaning together beyond theory and practice. Education and Culture, 29(2), 5–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, P., & Read, R. (2013). Practising pragmatist-Wittgensteinianism. In A. Malachowski (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to pragmatism (pp. 159–188). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, V. (2013). Dissonant voices: Philosophy, children’s literature, and perfectionist education (Dissertation). Stockholm: Stockholm University, Department of Education.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, V. (2015). Questions from the rough ground: Teaching, autobiography and the cosmopolitan ‘I’. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 34(5), 441–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mulhall, S. (2001). Inheritance and originality: Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Kierkegaard. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, R. (2007). Philosophy for life: Applying philosophy in politics and culture. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stickney, J. (2008). Wittgenstein’s ‘relativity’: Training in language-games and agreement in forms of life. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 40(5), 621–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations (4th revised ed.). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing (PI).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). On certainty. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing (OC).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1978). Remarks on the foundations of mathematics (3rd revised ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell Publishing (RFM).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Culture and value. (G. H. von Wright Ed., in collaboration with H. Nyman and P. Winch, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell (CV).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Viktor Johansson .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Johansson, V. (2017). The Weight of Dogmatism: Investigating “Learning” in Dewey’s Pragmatism and Wittgenstein’s Ordinary Language Philosophy. In: Peters, M., Stickney, J. (eds) A Companion to Wittgenstein on Education. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-3136-6_22

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-3136-6_22

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-10-3134-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-10-3136-6

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics