Skip to main content

‘Diagrammatic Teaching’: The Role of Iconic Signs in Meaningful Pedagogy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Edusemiotics – A Handbook

Abstract

Charles S. Peirce’s semiotics uniquely divides signs into: (i) symbols, which pick out their objects by arbitrary convention or habit , (ii) indices, which pick out their objects by unmediated ‘pointing’, and (iii) icons, which pick out their objects by resembling them (as Peirce put it: an icon’s parts are related in the same way that the objects represented by those parts are themselves related). Thus representing structure is one of the icon’s greatest strengths. It is argued that the implications of scaffolding education iconically are profound: for providing learners with a navigable road-map of a subject matter, for enabling them to see further connections of their own in what is taught, and for supporting meaningful active learning. Potential objections that iconic teaching is excessively entertaining and overly susceptible to misleading rhetorical manipulation are addressed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In the same volume Peirce’s former student Christine Ladd-Franklin also wrote a testimonial which was more critical, noting an “apparent aloofness and air of irresponsibility”, but adding that in the classroom, “[h]e got his effect…by creating the impression that we had before us a profound, original, dispassionate and impassioned seeker of truth” (Ladd-Franklin 1916, pp. 716–717).

  2. 2.

    Of course this is an emotionally charged example and one might wonder what are the limits of this model of interpretation? Could it be applied for instance to mathematics? Yes, even here Peirce claims that all three stages of interpretation are operative and vital. Hence the widely-acknowledged role of aesthetic appreciation (emotional interpretation) at the highest levels of mathematics, driven by an eros (energetic interpretation) not toward deductively valid arguments, which are a dime a dozen in the field, but so-called ‘elegant solutions’.

  3. 3.

    Yet again a reference to Plato’s philosophy is irresistible at this point—namely the claim towards the end of the Meno that what differentiates knowledge from mere belief is that it is ‘tethered’ so that it cannot ‘run off’. Indeed, perhaps Plato’s eidos or Form, with its strong (yet today strangely unremarked) visual connotations might have been precisely a semiotic concept reaching towards Peirce’s icon—rather than a useless entity sitting ‘in Heaven’ inviting Ockhamist elimination.

References

  • Brent, J. (1998). Charles Sanders Peirce: A life. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (2002). The logical syntax of language (A. Smeaton, Trans.). Chicago: Open Court Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colapietro, V. (2013). Neglected facets of Peirce’s ‘Speculative’ rhetoric’. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 45(7), 712–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoopes, J. (1998). Community denied: The wrong turn of pragmatic liberalism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Houser, N. (1986). Introduction. In The writings of Charles S. Peirce (Vol. 4: 1879–1884, pp. xix–lxx). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Houser, N. (1987). Toward a Peircean semiotic theory of learning. The American Journal of Semiotics, 5(2), 251–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jappy, T. (2013). Introduction to Peircean visual semiotics. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jastrow, J. (1916). Charles S. Peirce as a teacher. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 13(26), 723–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladd-Franklin, C. (1916). Charles S. Peirce at the Johns Hopkins. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 13(26), 715–722.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Legg, C. (2008). The problem of the essential icon. American Philosophical Quarterly, 45(3), 207–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legg, C. (2014). Charles Peirce’s limit concept of truth. Philosophy Compass, 9(3), 204–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1969). Convention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lizska, J. J. (1996). A general introduction to the semeiotic of Charles S. Peirce. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lizska, J. J. (2013). Charles Peirce’s rhetoric and the pedagogy of active learning. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 45(7), 781–788.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, R. E. (Ed.). (2014). The Cambridge handbook of multimedia learning (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931–1935; 1958). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (Vols. 1–6, C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss, Eds.; Vols. 7 and 8, A. Burks, Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [cited as CP].

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1976). Truth by convention, reprinted in The ways of paradox (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saussure, F. de (1916). Nature of the linguistic sign. In C. Bally & A. Sechehaye (Eds.), Cours de Linguistique Générale [Course in general linguistics]. New York: McGraw Hill Education.

    Google Scholar 

  • Semetsky, I. (Ed.). (2005). Peirce and education. Special issue of Educational Philosophy and Theory, 37(2).

    Google Scholar 

  • Semetsky, I. (2013). The edusemiotics of images: Essays on the art~science of Tarot. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Semetsky, I., & Stables, A. (Eds.). (2014). Pedagogy and edusemiotics: Theoretical challenges/practical opportunities. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Short, T. L. (1997). Peirce’s theory of signs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stables, A., & Semetsky, I. (2015). Edusemiotics: Semiotic philosophy as educational foundation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology: An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strand, T. (2005). Peirce on education: Nurturing the first rule of reason. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 24(3), 309–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Catherine Legg .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Science+Business Media Singapore

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Legg, C. (2017). ‘Diagrammatic Teaching’: The Role of Iconic Signs in Meaningful Pedagogy. In: Semetsky, I. (eds) Edusemiotics – A Handbook. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-1495-6_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-1495-6_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-10-1493-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-10-1495-6

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics