Advertisement

Future-Directed Opining Verbs and Negation

  • Melanie Bervoets
Chapter
  • 94 Downloads
Part of the Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy book series (SLAP, volume 102)

Abstract

The exceptional licensing of strict NPIs in embedded contexts is often tied to the unexpected “Neg-raised” readings found when negating certain attitude verbs. Both phenomena arise (sometimes in slightly modified form) when stative future-directed opining predicates are negated as well, and here too their nearly identical distributions mount a strong case for a derivational connection. On α, the strategy that attributes to each future-directed opining verb an attestation element and a modal element, we are able to treat the traditional Neg-raisers and the future-directed opining verbs together with respect to this data, a move that takes advantage of machinery independently required, and one supported by a shared set of characteristics, including optionality, stativity, cyclicity, and the availability of wide scope existential interpretations. Along with these Neg-raising and future-directed opining contexts, habitual and overtly dispositional sentences make up a class that can be called the “Neg” environments, and treating them as a single group, we can evaluate whether existing accounts of Neg-raising have the resources to address the full corresponding range of unexpected negative readings. Due to the shape of these readings, and what appears to be a more fundamental tie between Negand opinion states than between Negand lexical items, syntactic accounts are less applicable than those rooted in the excluded middle inference of Bartsch (Linguistische Berichte 27, 1973). Among these approaches, pragmatic theories are better equipped to incorporate a critical reliance on relevance, required to understand the cyclicity patterns and contexts where two or more different Negreadings are available.

Keywords

Negation Neg-raising Strict NPI licensing Opinion verbs Propositional attitude verbs Habituality Dispositions Implicature Exhaustification Relevance 

References

  1. Abusch, D. 2005. Triggering from alternative sets and projection of pragmatic presuppositons. Ms. Cornell University.Google Scholar
  2. Bar-Lev, Moshe E., and Danny Fox. 2017. Universal free choice and innocent inclusion. Semantics and Linguistic Theory 27: 95–115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bartsch, R. 1973. “Negative transportation” gibt es nicht. Linguistische Berichte 27: 1–7.Google Scholar
  4. Chierchia, G., and S. McConnell-Ginet. 1990. Meaning and grammar: An introduction to semantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Chierchia, Gennaro, Danny Fox, and Benjamin Spector. 2012. The grammatical view of scalar implicatures and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning, vol. 1, ed. C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, and Paul Portner. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  6. Collins, Chris, and Paul M. Postal. 2014. Classical NEG raising: An essay on the syntax of negation. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Fauconnier, Gilles. 1975. Polarity and the scale principle. Chicago Linguistics Society 11: 188–199.Google Scholar
  8. Fauconnier, Gilles. 1979. Implication reversal in a natural language. In Formal semantics and pragmatics for natural languages, ed. Franz Guenthner and S. J. Schmidt, 289–302. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  9. Fillmore, C. 1963. The position of embedding transformations in grammar. Word 19: 208–231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. von Fintel, Kai. 1999. NPI licensing, Strawson entailment, and context dependency. Journal of Semantics 16(2): 97–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fox, Danny. 2007. Free choice and the theory of scalar implicatures. Presupposition and Implicature in Compositional Semantics 71: 112.Google Scholar
  12. Fox, Danny, and Roni Katzir. 2011. On the characterization of alternatives. Natural Language Semantics 19: 87–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Gajewski, Jon Robert. 2007. Neg-raising and polarity. Linguistics and Philosophy 30: 289–328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Gajewski, Jon Robert. 2011. Licensing strong NPIs. Natural Language Semantics 19(2):109–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Giannakidou, A. 2002. UNTIL, aspect and negation: A novel argument for two untils. In Proceedings from SALT XII, ed. B. Jackson, 84–103. Ithaca: CLC Publications.Google Scholar
  16. Giannakidou, Anastasia. 1997. The landscape of polarity items. Rijksuniversiteit Groningen dissertation.Google Scholar
  17. Green, Georgia M. 1974. Semantics and syntactic regularity. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Groenendijk, G., and M. Stokhof. 1984. Studies on the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers. University of Amsterdam dissertation.Google Scholar
  19. Guerzoni, Elena, and Yael Sharvit. 2007. A question of strength: On NPIs in interrogative clauses. Linguistics and Philosophy 30(3): 361–391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Hacquard, Valentine. 2010. On the event relativity of modal auxiliaries. Natural Language Semantics 18: 79–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Heim, Irene. 1983. On the projection problem for presuppositions. In Proceedings of the North East Linguistics Society 14, ed. M. Barlow, D. Flickinger, and M. Westcoat, 114–126. University of Stanford.Google Scholar
  22. Heim, Irene. 1992. Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics 9: 183–221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Heim, Irene. 2011. Pragmatics class lecture notes. Cambridge: MIT.Google Scholar
  24. Homer, Vincent. 2012. Neg-raising and positive polarity: The view from modals. Semantics and Pragmatics (accepted with minor revisions).Google Scholar
  25. Horn, Laurence. 1971. Negative transportation: Unsafe at any speed? CLS 7: 120–133.Google Scholar
  26. Horn, Laurence. 1978. Remarks on Neg-raising. Syntax and Semantics 9: 129–220.Google Scholar
  27. Horn, Laurence. 2014. The cloud of unknowing. In Black book: A festschrift in honor of Frans Zwarts, ed. Jack Hoeksema and Dicky Gilbers, 178–196. Groningen: University of Groningen.Google Scholar
  28. Horn, Laurence, and Samuel Bayer. 1984. Short-circuited implicature: A negative contribution. Linguistics and Philosophy 7(4): 397–414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Jespersen, Otto. 1917. Negation in English and other languages. Copenhagen: A. F. Høst.Google Scholar
  30. Karttunen, Lauri. 1974a. Presuppositions and linguistic context. Theoretical Linguistics 1: 181–193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Karttunen, Lauri. 1974b. Until. Chicago Linguistics Society 10: 284–297.Google Scholar
  32. Klima, Edward. 1964. Negation in English. In The structure of language, ed. Jerry Fodor and Jerrold Katz, New York: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  33. Ladusaw, William. 1979. Polarity sensitivity as inherent scope relations. University of Texas at Austin dissertation.Google Scholar
  34. Ladusaw, William. 1980a. Affective ‘or’, factive verbs, and negative polarity items. In Papers from the sixteenth regional meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, ed. J. Kreiman and A.E. Ojeda, 170–184. Chicago: University of Chicago.Google Scholar
  35. Ladusaw, William. 1980b. On the notion “affective” in the analysis of negative polarity items. Journal of Linguistic Research 1: 1–23.Google Scholar
  36. Lakoff, Robin. 1969. A syntactic argument for negative transportation. CLS 5: 149–157.Google Scholar
  37. Lindholm, James. 1969. Chicago Linguistics Society 5: 148–158.Google Scholar
  38. Linebarger, Marcia. 1980. The grammar of negative polarity. MIT dissertation.Google Scholar
  39. Linebarger, Marcia. 1987. Negative polarity and grammatical representation. Linguistics and Philosophy 10: 325–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Roberts, C. 2004. Context in dynamic interpretation. In Handbook of pragmatics, ed. Laurence Horn and G. Ward. Hoboken: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  41. Romoli, Jacopo. 2013. A scalar implicature-based approach to neg-raising. Linguistics and Philosophy 36: 291–353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Simons, Mandy. 2001. On the conversational basis of some presuppositions. In Proceedings of SALT XI, ed. R. Hastings, B. Jackson, and Z. Zvolensky. Ithaca: CLC Publications.Google Scholar
  43. Zwarts, F. 1998. Three types of polarity. In Plural quantification, ed. F. Hamm and E. Hinrichs, 177–238. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  • Melanie Bervoets
    • 1
  1. 1.TorontoCanada

Personalised recommendations