Skip to main content

Distribution Effects

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Semantics of Opinion

Part of the book series: Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy ((SLAP,volume 102))

  • 195 Accesses

Abstract

Free choice inferences, or distribution effects, are well-known with modals and other quantifiers. This chapter shows that these inferences turn up with the future-directed opining verbs in analogous ways, with some of the verbs exhibiting the pattern associated with existential terms, and others displaying the pattern found with universals. We even see that among the universals, the verbs split into subclasses that correspond to weak and strong necessity. This symmetry between the future-directed opining verbs and the better studied quantifiers motivates the pursuit of a unified account of free choice that can derive the correct inferences in all environments. In general, a scalar implicature based approach to free choice has been widely (though not universally) accepted, and the grammatical theories in this family have the ability to effectively deal with embedding contexts, something required to generate the future-directed opining data demonstrated here. These theories, such as Bar-Lev and Fox (Universal free choice and innocent inclusion. In: Semantics and linguistic theory, vol 27, pp 95–115, 2017), are also easily tied to a notion of relevance that can account for the context-sensitivity of inferences found with universal constructions, including the universal future-directed opining verbs. Additionally, a grammatical approach can help to explain the presence of distribution inferences with modal-based wide disjunctions (including with the future-directed opining verbs), but not with other wide disjunctions. But while the potential power of these approaches affords them the ability to capture a broader range of inferences, it also necessitates a principled deployment that can maintain a coherent overall picture of exhaustification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Note that there is a sense in which giving money and giving a hotel stay are possible—epistemically, these are the possibilities provided by the speaker. This is fine: there is an epistemic/ignorance reading of the sentences of (128131) and (133145) as well; the critical point is that there is no non-epistemic, non-speaker-ignorance way to interpret the disjuncts in this extensional case.

  2. 2.

    For the purposes of the disjunctive distributive patterns at issue in this work, this intuitive notion of scale will suffice, though it should be mentioned that this idea requires revision in order to precisely constrain the alternatives at play in deriving a wider range of implicatures. Several proposals have been built for this purpose, particularly around monotonicity (e.g. Horn 1989 and Matsumoto 1995) and complexity (e.g. Atlas and Levinson 1981 and Katzir 2007).

  3. 3.

    For additional motivation behind these features, as well as a slightly different way to formulate a response, see Spector (2006). Also note that even though Sauerland’s arguments are guided by neo-Gricean principles, both suggestions he tables have been adopted by non-globalist accounts as well. See, e.g., Fox (2007).

  4. 4.

    The alternatives in (201) are propositional, but this is just a notational convenience: really it is or that is originally associated with alternatives, and then these grow with the structure. For instance:

    1. (1)

      (a) ALT(a cookie or a banana) = {a cookie or a banana, a cookie and a banana, a cookie, a banana}

      (b) ALT(Myron ate a cookie or a banana) = {Myron ate a cookie or a banana, Myron ate a cookie and a banana, Myron ate a cookie, Myron ate a banana}

  5. 5.

    Here we employ an informal modal logic formulation that we will use throughout, especially in the later chapters, when our semantic calculations start to get unwieldy.

  6. 6.

    To calculate these alternatives, I have applied IE and II to each original alternative, and then simplified as much as possible. The details of recursive exhaustification are relegated to a footnote in Bar-Lev and Fox (2017), but I believe this is their intention. Errors of assumption are, of course, entirely mine.

  7. 7.

    Note that the discussion in Crnič et al. (2015) was concerned with missing universal inferences, in particular ¬ ∀x(p(x)) and ¬ ∀x(q(x)). With the account of free choice presented in Bar-Lev and Fox (2017), we no longer predict that these alternatives will be innocently excludable, so the original worry is assuaged. However, as discussed here, the conjunctive alternatives are still innocently excludable, and so the spirit of the concern persists.

  8. 8.

    If the conjunctive alternatives were pruned during the process of exhaustification, we’d end up being able to innocently include all the other alternatives, including ∀xpx and ∀xqx, leading to an interpretation of (227) as Every brother of mine has been married to a woman and a man, a reading that is not attested.

  9. 9.

    It may be worth mentioning that both examples are still meaningful, but attempting to read the to clause the same way we do for the other examples (as something like if you want to get from Paris to London), brings about a feeling that the second clause has slightly shifted the topic of conversation.

  10. 10.

    Note that the contextual assumption of taking up a single option (for (261), an afternoon activity) is an idea that requires more elaboration. Here, I will assume that it forms a part of the conversational background for any weak necessity modal or verb, including in (262), where it would restrict the initial set of good worlds to those in which you get to London via the standard number of transportation options, namely one. It could be that something like a conditional assumption where things (goals, desires, commitments, etc.) come about or are achieved by way of the normal number of contextually determined alternatives is present with all modals, however, the key difference between the weak and strong necessity terms will still be that for the former, the first ordering source establishes that the thing (goal, desire, commitment, etc.) is achieved, and the second ordering source selects among the alternatives for doing so, while for the latter, the single ordering source only asserts which alternatives are requisites for achieving the thing (goal, desire, commitment, etc.).

References

  • Aloni, Maria. 2003. Free choice in modal contexts. In Proceedings of sinn und bedeutung, vol. 7, 25–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aloni, Maria. 2007. Free choice, modals, and imperatives. Natural Language Semantics 15(1): 65–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alonso-Ovalle, Luis. 2005. Distributing the disjuncts over the modal space. In Proceedings of the 35th north east linguistics society conference, ed. Leah Bateman and Cherlon Ussery. University of Massachusetts, Amherst: GLSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alonso-Ovalle, Luis. 2006. Disjunction in alternative semantics: University of Massachusetts, Amherst dissertation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, Jay David, and Stephen C. Levinson. 1981. It-clefts, informativeness and logical form: Radical pragmatics (Revised Standard Version). In Radical pragmatics, ed. P. Cole, 1–61. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Lev, Moshe E., and Danny Fox. 2017. Universal free choice and innocent inclusion. Semantics and Linguistic Theory 27: 95–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemla, Emmanuel. 2009. Universal implicatures and free choice effects: Experimental data. Semantics and Pragmatics 2(1): 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemla, Emmanuel, and Lewis Bott. 2014. Processing inferences at the semantics/pragmatics frontier: Disjunctions and free choice. Cognition 130(3): 380–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Gennaro, Danny Fox, and Benjamin Spector. 2012. The grammatical view of scalar implicatures and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning, ed. C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, and Paul Portner, vol. 1. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Giorgio. 2004. Scalar implicatures, polarity phenomena, and the syntax/pragmatics interface. In Structures and beyond, ed. A. Belletti. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ciardelli, Ivano, Jeroen Groenendijk, and Floris Roelofsen. 2009. Attention! ‘might’ in inquistive semantics. Semantics and Linguistic Theory 19: 91–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crnič, Luka, Emmanuel Chemla, and Danny Fox. 2015. Scalar implicatures of embedded disjunction. Natural Language Semantics 23(4): 271–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, Kai, and Sabine Iatridou. 2005. What to do if you want to go to Harlem: Anankastic conditionals and related matters. Manuscript, MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, Kai, and Sabine Iatridou. 2008. How to say ought in foreign: The composition of weak necessity modals. In Time and modality. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 2007. Free choice and the theory of scalar implicatures. Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics 71: 112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazdar, G. 1979. Pragmatics. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, Bart. 2005. Entertaining alternatives: Disjunctions as modals. Natural Language Semantics 13(4): 383–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, Bart. 2010. Quantity implicatures. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gotzner, Nicole, and Jacopo Romoli. 2017. The scalar inferences of strong scalar terms under negative quantifiers and constraints on the theory of alternatives. Journal of Semantics 35(1): 95–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. Paul. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Syntax and semantics, vol. 3: Speech acts, 41–58. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, G., and M. Stokhof. 1984. Studies on the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers: University of Amsterdam dissertation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence. 1972. On the semantic properties of logical operators: UCLA dissertation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence. 1989. A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence. 2006. The border wars: A neo-Gricean perspective. Where Semantics Meets Pragmatics 16: 21–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, Hans. 1973. Free choice permission. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 74, 57–74. The Aristotelian Society Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, Hans. 1978. Semantics versus pragmatics. In Formal semantics and pragmatics for natural languages, 255–287. Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Katzir, Roni. 2007. Structurally-defined alternatives. Linguistics and Philosophy 30(6): 669–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katzir, Roni. 2014. On the roles of markedness and contradiction in the use of alternatives. In Pragmatics, semantics and the case of scalar implicatures, 40–71. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klinedinst, Nathan Winter. 2007. Plurality and possibility: UCLA dissertation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 1981. The notional category of modality. In Words, worlds, and contexts: New approaches in word semantics, ed. H.J. Eikmeyer and H. Rieser, 38–74. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 1991. Modality. In Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research, ed. A. von Stechow and D. Wunderlich, 639–650. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika, and Junko Shimoyama. 2002. Indeterminate pronouns: The view from japanese. In Proceedings of the third tokyo conference on psycholinguistics, ed. Yukio Otsu, 1–25. Tokyo: Hituzi Syobo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroch, Anthony. 1972. Lexical and inferred meanings for some time adverbs. Quarterly Progress Reports of the Research Laboratory of Electronics 104: 260–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, Fred. 1998. Plurals and maximalization. In Events and grammar, ed. Susan Rothstein, 237–272. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Matsumoto, Yo. 1995. The conversational condition on horn scales. Linguistics and Philosophy 18(1): 21–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, Marie-Christine. 2015. Generalized free choice and missing alternatives. Journal of Semantics 33(4): 703–754.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. 1997. Intensional verbs and quantifiers. Natural Language Semantics 5: 1–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. 1953. Reference and modality. In From a logical point of view. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Benjamin. 2006. Against grammatical computation of scalar implicatures. Journal of Semantics 23(4): 361–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, Uli. 2004. Scalar implicatures in complex sentences. Linguistics and Philosophy 27: 367–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons, Mandy. 2005. Dividing things up: The semantics of or and the modal/or interaction. Natural Language Semantics 13(3): 271–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloman, Aaron. 1970. ‘ought’ and ‘better’. Mind 79(315): 385–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spector, Benjamin. 2003. Scalar implicatures: exhaustivity and gricean reasoning. In Proceedings of ESSLLI, vol. 3, 277–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spector, Benjamin. 2006. Aspects de la pragmatique des operateurs logiques: Université Paris 7 dissertation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Rooij, Robert, and Katrin Schulz. 2004. Exhaustive interpretation of complex sentences. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 13(4): 491–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Tiel, Bob, Emiel Van Miltenburg, Natalia Zevakhina, and Bart Geurts. 2016. Scalar diversity. Journal of Semantics 33(1): 137–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmermann, Thomas Ede. 2000. Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility. Natural Language Semantics 8(4): 255–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature B.V.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bervoets, M. (2020). Distribution Effects. In: The Semantics of Opinion. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol 102. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-1747-0_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-1747-0_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-024-1746-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-024-1747-0

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics