The Semantics of Opinion pp 1-12 | Cite as
Introduction
- 94 Downloads
Abstract
The empirical domain introduced here is a class of verbs whose members can be used to describe reports of opinion regarding future possibilities. Investigating the semantic nature of these “future-directed opining verbs”—including recommend, offer, and promise—involves an examination of several key properties, which also throws into relief what the verbs have in common with both the propositional attitudes and the speech reporting verbs, and where these groups diverge. Among the basic dimensions at play are compatibility with different kinds of subjects and objects, the types of events the verbs can describe, the presence or absence of a requirement for external attestation, and how the verbs combine with a dispositional operator. The future-directed opining verbs also interact with two important phenomena most commonly associated with modal quantifiers and attitudes, respectively, namely free choice disjunction and Neg-raising. Resulting expansions to the set of contexts where each applies set up critical examinations of existing theories, forming the secondary subject matter of this work.
References
- Abusch, D. 1997. Sequence of tense and temporal de re. Linguistics and Philosophy 20(1): 1–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Abusch, D. 1998. Sequence of tense, intensionality and scope. In The proceedings of the 7th west coast conference on formal linguistics, ed. Hagit Borer. The Stanford Linguistics Association.Google Scholar
- Alonso-Ovalle. 2006. Disjunction in alternative semantics: University of Massachusetts, Amherst dissertation.Google Scholar
- Anand, Pranav, and Valentine Hacquard. 2008. Epistemics with attitude. In SALT XVIII, ed. T. Friedman and S. Ito. Ithaca: Cornell University.Google Scholar
- Bar-Lev, Moshe E., and Danny Fox. 2017. Universal free choice and innocent inclusion. Semantics and Linguistic Theory 27: 95–115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bartsch, R. 1973. “Negative transportation” gibt es nicht. Linguistische Berichte 27: 1–7.Google Scholar
- Beck, S., and K. Johnson. 2004. Double objects again. Linguistic Inquiry 35(1): 97–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Boneh, Nora, and Edit Doron. 2008. Habituality and the habitual aspect. In Theoretical and crosslinguistic approaches to the semantics of aspect, ed. Susan Rothstein, 321–347. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Boneh, Nora, and Edit Doron. 2009. Modal and temporal aspects of habituality. In Syntax, lexical semantics, and event structure, ed. M. Rappaport-Hovav, E. Doron, and I. Sichel. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Boneh, Nora, and Edit Doron. 2013. Hab and Gen in the expression of habituality. Genericity 43: 176–191.Google Scholar
- Burge, T. 1977. Belief de re. The Journal of Philosophy 74(6): 338–362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Carlson, Gregory. 1977. Reference to kinds in English: University of Massachusetts, Amherst dissertation.Google Scholar
- Chierchia, Gennaro, Danny Fox, and Benjamin Spector. 2012. The grammatical view of scalar implicatures and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning, ed. C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, and Paul Portner, vol. 1. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
- Collins, Chris, and Paul M. Postal. 2014. Classical NEG raising: An essay on the syntax of negation. Cambridge, MA: MIT.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Crnič, Luka, Emmanuel Chemla, and Danny Fox. 2015. Scalar implicatures of embedded disjunction. Natural Language Semantics 23(4): 271–305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Dowty, David. 1986. The effects of aspectual class on the temporal structure of discourse: Semantics or pragmatics? Linguistics and Philosophy 9(1): 37–61.Google Scholar
- Fillmore, C. 1963. The position of embedding transformations in grammar. Word 19: 208–231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Fodor, J.D. 1970. The linguistic description of opaque contexts. MIT dissertation.Google Scholar
- Fox, Danny. 2007. Free choice and the theory of scalar implicatures. Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics 71: 112.Google Scholar
- Gajewski, Jon Robert. 2007. Neg-raising and polarity. Linguistics and Philosophy 30: 289–328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Homer, Vincent. 2012. Neg-raising and positive polarity: The view from modals. Semantics and Pragmatics (accepted with minor revisions).Google Scholar
- Horn, Laurence. 1971. Negative transportation: Unsafe at any speed? CLS 7: 120–133.Google Scholar
- Horn, Laurence. 1972. On the semantic properties of logical operators. UCLA dissertation.Google Scholar
- Horn, Laurence. 1978. Remarks on Neg-raising. Syntax and Semantics 9: 129–220.Google Scholar
- Horn, Laurence. 2014. The cloud of unknowing. In Black book: A festschrift in honor of Frans Zwarts, ed. Jack Hoeksema and Dicky Gilbers, 178–196. Groningen: University of Groningen. 178–196.Google Scholar
- Horn, Laurence, and Samuel Bayer. 1984. Short-circuited implicature: A negative contribution. Linguistics and Philosophy 7(4): 397–414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kamp, Hans. 1973. Free choice permission. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 74, 57–74. London: The Aristotelian Society Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
- Klinedinst, Nathan Winter. 2007. Plurality and possibility. UCLA dissertation.Google Scholar
- Kratzer, Angelika. 1998. More structural analogies between pronouns and tenses. Semantics and Linguistic Theory 8: 92–110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Krifka, Manfred, Francis Jeffrey Pelletier, Gregory N. Carlson, Alice ter Meulen, Gennaro Chierchia, and Godehard Link. 1995. Genericity: An introduction. In The generic book, ed. Gregory Carlson and Francis Jeffrey Pelletier. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
- Lakoff, Robin. 1969. A syntactic argument for negative transportation. CLS 5: 149–157.Google Scholar
- Lewis, David. 1979. Attitude de dicto and de se. The Philosophical Review 88(4): 513–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Menendez-Benito, Paula. 2012. On dispositional sentences. Genericity 43: 276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Meyer, Marie-Christine. 2015. Generalized free choice and missing alternatives. Journal of Semantics 33(4): 703–754.Google Scholar
- Ogihara, Toshiyuki. 2013. In Tense, attitudes, and scope, vol. 58. Springer Science and Business Media.Google Scholar
- Partee, B.H. 1974. Opacity and scope. In Semantics and Philosophy, ed. Milton K. Munitz and Peter K. Unger, 81–101. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
- Quine, W.V.O. 1956. Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy 53(5): 177–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Rimell, Laura. 2004. Habitual sentences and generic quantification. In Proceedings of WCCFL, ed. G. Garding and M. Tsujimura, vol. 23, 663–676.Google Scholar
- Romoli, Jacopo. 2013. A scalar implicature-based approach to neg-raising. Linguistics and Philosophy 36: 291–353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Rothstein, Susan. 2004. Structuring events. Blackwell Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Russell, Bertrand. 1919. On propositions: What they are and how they mean. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 2: 1–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Sauerland, Uli. 2004. Scalar implicatures in complex sentences. Linguistics and Philosophy 27: 367–391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Simons, Mandy. 2005. Dividing things up: The semantics of or and the modal/or interaction. Natural Language Semantics 13(3): 271–316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- von Stechow, A. 2002. Binding by verbs: Tense, person and mood under attitudes. In Proceedings of the 33rd North East Linguistics Society Meeting, ed. Makoto Kadowaki and Shigeto Kawahara, 379–403. Amherst: GLSA.Google Scholar
- Vendler, Zeno. 1957. Verbs and times. Philosophical Review LXVI: 143–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Zimmermann, Thomas Ede. 2000. Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility. Natural Language Semantics 8(4): 255–290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Zucchi, Sandro. 1998. Aspect shift. In Events and grammar, ed. Susan Rothstein. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar