Skip to main content

Plural Identities and Preference Formation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Agency, Freedom and Choice

Part of the book series: Theory and Decision Library A: ((TDLA,volume 53))

  • 301 Accesses

Abstract

In Chap. 2 I argued that an approach that aims to capture freedom’s agency value has to account for the value the availability of choice options has for a person’s deliberation about her values and goals before making decisions. Before addressing this question in greater detail in Chap. 5, I pose the question how this picture of a person reflecting upon a plurality of motives, as widely employed in the philosophy of action, relates to the assumption that a person’s (rational) choices can be represented by a transitive, all-things-considered preference over the alternatives, as is commonly assumed in rational choice theory and the freedom ranking literature. Under which conditions can a person indeed form a transitive, all-things-considered preference from a set of plural (possibly conflicting) values, or as I call it, from her plural identities? I make use of a social choice framework in order to explore this question and illustrate the task the person is facing as an intra-personal aggregation problem: a person has to derive his (transitive) all-things-considered preference from a profile of preference relations reflecting his plural identity. This chapter is a slightly modified version of Binder (Soc Choice Welf 42:959–976, 2014).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is important to be aware of the ‘double use’ of the concept of preference in economic analysis. Preferences are used ‘as the basis of welfare judgements’ or as descriptions of one’s choices (Sen 1973, 253).

  2. 2.

    For a discussion of pleasure or desire satisfaction accounts, see Griffin (1986).

  3. 3.

    In addition to transitivity, a person’s preferences are commonly required to be complete. In this chapter the focus is on transitivity. For an investigation of utility theory without the assumption that a person’s preferences are complete, see Aumann (1962). For studies of the formal connection between multi-objective decision making and completeness of a person’s preferences, see Ok (2002) and Dubra et al. (2004).

  4. 4.

    Strictly speaking this example illustrates a case of quasi-transitivity (rather than transitivity). In the framework I adopt in this chapter, which only allows for strict preferences, the two coincide.

  5. 5.

    The crucial points of disagreement between Frankfurt and Watson concern, inter alia, the status of second-order desires: Frankfurt (1971) fails – according to Watson (1973, 218) – to explain what gives them the special status of being the person’s own desires. Furthermore, they disagree on whether agency is about formulating values over courses of actions (one might not have previously desired) or about an internal process in which the agent forms second-order desires over a set of given desires Watson (1973, 219). The stance on these points does not affect the argument presented here. What is relevant is that a person reflects on a set of values or desires in the process of choice.

  6. 6.

    This conception of a person’s identity and the problem addressed with it differs from the way the term is commonly employed in philosophy. The problem of identity over time is prominent in metaphysics. Which conditions have to be satisfied in order to say that a person or object at one point in time is the same as at a later point in time? Is a person who loses her memory in a car accident identical to the person she was before? Is a person after a heart transplant identical to the person before? The main question is whether one can establish criteria of personal identity. One can distinguish between physical and psychological criteria. Roughly speaking, the first demands the physical continuity over time of a person’s brain and/or body, whereas the latter requires the continuity of a person’s memory over time. For a collection of seminal contributions within the philosophical identity debate, see Noonan (1993). For a discussion of different criteria of personal identity, see Parfit (1984, chap. 10) and Raymond and Barresi (2003). For a survey of logical approaches to the metaphysical problem of identity, see Hawthorne (2003).

  7. 7.

    Strictly speaking, the case in which a person’s identity is ‘singular’ is a special case of the proposed framework.

  8. 8.

    Strictly speaking, the generality of the framework adopted here does not presuppose any view of the source of a person’s various identity parts. These can be related to her social surroundings and the groups she identifies with, but they do not have to be. What is important, though, is that I refer only to those identity parts with which the person herself identifies; I neglect the way external ascriptions can affect (and constrain) a person’s identity. For a discussion of this point, see Sen (2006, 6–8, 31).

  9. 9.

    Note that this does not mean that a person can choose any identity, but rather that there are some choices among alternative combinations of identities (Sen 2006, 38).

  10. 10.

    The sole way in which a change in a person’s identity over time enters the analysis in this chapter is via one of the conditions imposed on the process in which he derives his all-things-considered preference from his plural identity. The monotonicity condition, which I introduce in Sect. 4.4, requires a certain continuity of the choices a person derives from her plural identity, in case the composition of her plural identity changes. For an analysis of a person’s plural identities, or multiple selves over time, see Heilmann (2008, sect. 4.3).

  11. 11.

    One of the classics in the analysis of decision making under the unresolved conflict of multiple objectives is Levi (1986). For a survey of the literature on multiple objectives decision making and a discussion of several different approaches, see Davis (2003), or Ellis (2006) on various approaches to the individual in economics in general and (rational) choice theory in particular.

  12. 12.

    For an introduction to social choice theory, see Gaertner (2006). For a survey of social choice theory, see Sen (1986a,b).

  13. 13.

    Hurley (1985) shows furthermore that conditions necessary to lead to single profile impossibilities violate supervenience in a similar way.

  14. 14.

    Sen, however, as far as I know, never used this point as part of an argument that Arrow’s impossibility is less problematic in an intra-personal context.

  15. 15.

    Strictly speaking, acyclicity is sufficient but not necessary for a binary relation R on X to induce a choice function if R is complete. I shall return to this issue in Sect. 4.6.

  16. 16.

    For an overview over different interpretations of incomparability and incommensurability, see Chang (1997).

  17. 17.

    Raz (1986, 347–348) raises a similar case when he argues that for many people it is inconsistent with their identity as parents to rank (compare) their child(ren) with sums of money.

  18. 18.

    Sen (1985, 2002, 2004) has contributed most extensively to the analysis of incompleteness of preferences in social and individual choice.

  19. 19.

    Note that for all x, y ∈ X if xNy then yNx.

  20. 20.

    Note that the usual definition of acyclicity, that is R on X is acyclic if, and only if, for all x 1, x 2, …, x j, j being a finite positive integer, x 1 Px 2, x 2 Px 3, …., x j−1 Px j implies x 1 Rx j, is equivalent to the definition adopted here if the preference relation is complete.

  21. 21.

    In Table 4.1 any two alternatives x and y which are not ranked vis-à-vis each other are denoted by [xy].

  22. 22.

    These differ, though, depending on the conditions imposed on the preference relations R on X.

  23. 23.

    There are other substantive and methodological reasons to impose Universal Domain: one is that we are interested in conditions which the Identity Aggregation Procedure of any person is supposed to satisfy. Thus the procedure is supposed to work for different persons, who are characterized by different identity profiles. Another (methodological) reason relates to the question the framework aims to address, namely under which conditions a person can indeed derive a transitive/acyclic all-things-considered preference. In order to gain a clear understanding of the structure of the aggregation problem at hand (and possible problems in a person’s preference formation) it is fruitful to start with the most admissible case, in order to then step-wisely restrict it in the light of emerging impossibility results.

  24. 24.

    Note that the first, narrow line of interpretation would allow a person to be, say, a Buddhist and a Christian ‘simultaneously’, since both are reflected by different dimensions (partial orderings) in the identity profile. The second, broader line of interpretation precludes this though, since Christian and Buddhist are reflected as different partial orderings in one (the same) dimension (religious belief, say) in the identity profile.

  25. 25.

    It is important to note, though, that unlike traditional psychological criteria of connectedness which are based on backward-looking memory (Parfit 1984, sect. 78), Bratman (2007, 29) and Parfit (1982, 2012) focus on forward-looking connections of a person’s plans and intentions.

  26. 26.

    Note that Monotonicity does not say anything about cases in which identity parts are added that are opposed to the previous all-things-considered preference, or in the case where a person gives up a part that ‘supported’ the former all-things-considered preference.

  27. 27.

    Kelsey (1986) discusses the counter-intuitive flavour of a weaker form of imposition in the case in which the various identity parts, or objectives as he calls them, are defined very narrowly.

  28. 28.

    To see the formal equivalence between profiles of quasi-transitive orderings and profiles of strict partial orderings, let for all x, y ∈ X, for all i ∈ M, [xN i y if, and only if, xI i y] and [yN i x if, and only if, yI i x]. Note that the relation N on X, as well as the relation I on X are symmetric and reflexive, but not transitive. If one reformulates the introduced conditions accordingly, the proofs of Theorems 4.1*–4.3* hold for the reformulated framework of quasi-transitive orderings.

  29. 29.

    The term ‘lexicographic procedure’ refers to the following aggregation procedure (based on Houy and Tadenuma (2009, 1771)), xPy if, and only if, (1) xP 1 y or (2) xN 1 y and xP 2 y, or …, or (m) xN 1 y, …, xN m−1 y and xP m y. The relation N on X is transitive if, and only if, for all x, y, z ∈ X, xNy and yNz implies xNz.

  30. 30.

    Contributions in the literature (Gibbard 1969; Weymark 1984) have shown that – over a domain of complete and transitive orderings – requiring the social ordering to be complete and quasi-transitive leads to oligarchies. An oligarchy is a set of individuals whose (i) unanimous strict preference over any two alternative x over y, implies x to be socially preferred to y; and (ii) the members of the oligarchy have veto-power, i.e. if some member of the oligarchy strictly prefers x over y, this implies that it is not the case that y is socially preferred to x. Furthermore, results in the judgment aggregation literature (Gärdenfors 2006; Dietrich and List 2008) indicate the emergence of ‘strong oligarchies’ if one allows for a domain of possibly incomplete judgement sets (Dietrich and List 2008, 27). In a social choice framework, strong oligarchies can be defined as a set of individuals who do not only dictate their unanimously held strict preferences on the social preference, but also dictate incompleteness between any two alternatives x and y which are not ranked by all members of the strong oligarchy. It can be shown that a strengthening of the Arrovian conditions to those employed in this article will imply the strong oligarchy to be a singleton which is equivalent to strong imposition as defined in this article.

  31. 31.

    This example is a slightly modified version of an example invoked by Pettit (2001, 284).

  32. 32.

    This example is based (very crudely) on the Borda procedure. For a more precise, formal exposition, see Gaertner (2006, 92–98).

  33. 33.

    Fishburn (1970) considers inter-personal aggregation problems over a domain of quasi-transitive preference profiles. The difference between Theorem 4.2 and his example (Fishburn 1970, 482) is that he illustrates the occurrence of cycles for m = 3 and #X = 3, whereas Theorem 4.2 of this article holds for m ≥ 2 and #X > 3. I am very grateful to an anonymous referee for making me aware of this point made by Fishburn.

  34. 34.

    Costello (2004, 2005) among others, has identified ‘identity dissonance’ as one possible reason for the persistent failure of affirmative action programmes in the classroom. This is mainly due to the fact that students, for whom the new professional identities at the relevant school are very new, or even stand in conflict with their other identity parts, need to spend much more time and energy on the resolution of internal conflicts, the monitoring of others and the understanding of the (implicit) rules that govern their new surroundings. Others (Thumma 1991) have explored the strategies people employ to resolve the value conflicts underlying their contradictory identities.

  35. 35.

    To be more precise, Fishburn (1970) is concerned with inter-personal aggregation problems and considers a sub-domain of profiles of quasi-transitive orderings. He shows that for his sub-domain simple majority rule yields a quasi-transitive social ordering. If indifference (I on X) between alternatives is replaced by incompleteness (N on X) in his definition, then it can be shown that Value Overlap is contained in his sub-domain (Definition A in Fishburn (1970, 484)), which in turn guarantees a transitive all-things-considered preference.

  36. 36.

    The condition Value Overlap in this article was inspired by Sen (1969) whose domain condition Value Restriction is sufficient for Majority Rule to generate quasi-transitive social preference orderings over a domain of profiles of weak orders. Pattanaik (1970) provides a generalization by establishing sufficient conditions for the class of binary, decisive, neutral, and non-negatively responsive social decision procedures to yield quasi-transitive social preferences over a domain of profiles of quasi-transitive individual preferences. It can be shown that the domain generated by Value Overlap is contained in Pattanaik’s domain condition VR* (Pattanaik 1970, 270).

  37. 37.

    Note, however, that Value Consistency is not contained in the sub-domain established by Fishburn (1970), nor in the sub-domain established by Pattanaik (1970).

  38. 38.

    Recall that a second interpretation of incompleteness adopted in this chapter was incompleteness as an irrelevance for a person’s identity part. This second interpretation, however, could plausibly be ‘taken over’ by indifference.

References

  • Arlegi and Teschl. 2015. Conflicts in Decision Making. In Individual and Collective Choice and Social Welfare; Essays in Honor of Nick Baigent, Studies in Choice and Welfare, ed. Constanze Binder, Giulio Codognato, Miriam Teschl, and Yongsheng Xu, 11–29. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, Kenneth J. 1951/1963. Social Choice and Individual Values. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, Robert J. 1962. Utility Theory Without the Completeness Axiom. Econometrica 30: 445–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baigent, Nick. 1995. Behind the Veil of Preference. The Japanese Economic Review 46: 88–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binder, Constanze. 2014. Plural Identities and Preference Formation. Social Choice and Welfare 42: 959–976.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, Michael E. 2000. Reflection, Planning, and Temporally Extended Agency. Philosophical Review 109: 35–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, Michael E. 2001. Two Problems About Human Agency. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 101: 309–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, Michael E. 2007. Structures of Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, Ruth. 1997. Introduction. In Incommensurability, Incompleteness and Practical Reason, ed. Ruth Chang, 1–34. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costello, Carrie Yang. 2004. Changing Clothes: Gender Inequality and Professional Socialization. NWSA Journal 16: 138–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costello, Carrie Yang. 2005. Professional Identity Crisis, Race, Class, Gender and Success at Professional Schools. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, John. 2003. The Theory of the Individual in Economics, Identity and Value. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, Franz, and Christian List. 2008. Judgment Aggregation Without Full Rationality. Social Choice and Welfare 31: 15–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubra, Juan, Fabio Maccheroni, and Efe A. Ok. 2004. Expected Utility Theory Without the Completeness Axiom. Journal of Economic Theory 115: 118–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, Stephen. 2006. Multiple Objectives: A Neglected Problem in the Theory of Human Action. Synthese 153: 313–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, Peter C. 1970. Intransitive Individual Indifference and Transitive Majorities. Econometrica 38: 481–489.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry G. 1971. Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person. Journal of Philosophy 68: 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaertner, Wulf. 2006. A Primer in Social Choice Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, Peter. 2006. An Arrow-Like Theorem for Voting with Logical Consequences. Economics & Philosophy 22: 181–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, Allan. 1969. Intransitive Social Indifference and the Arrow Dilemma. Working Paper, University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, James. 1986. Well-Being. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, John. 2003. Identity. In The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, ed. Michael J. Loux, and Dean W. Zimmerman, 99–130. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heilmann, Conrad. 2008. A representation of time discounting. CPNSS working paper, vol. 4, no. 6. The Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science (CPNSS), London School of Economics, London, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Houy, Nicolas, and Koichi Tadenuma. 2009. Lexicographic Compositions of Multiple Criteria for Decision Making. Journal of Economic Theory 144: 1770–1782.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, Susan L. 1985. Supervenience and the Possibility of Coherence. Mind 376: 501–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, Richard C. 1974. Preference Among Preferences. The Journal of Philosophy 71: 377–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelsey, David. 1986. Utility and the Individual: An Analysis of Internal Conflicts. Social Choice and Welfare 3: 77–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krause, Ulrich, and Ian Steedman. 1986. Goethe’s Faust, Arrow’s Possibility Theorem and the Individual Decision Taker. In The Multiple Self, ed. Jon Elster, 197–231. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, Isaac. 1986. Hard choices: Decision making under unresolved conflict. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • May, Kenneth O. 1954. Intransitivity, Utility, and the Aggregation of Preference Patterns. Econometrica 22: 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noonan, Harold. 1993. Identity. The International Research Library of Philosophy. Aldershot: Dartmouth Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ok, Efe K. 2002. Utility Representation on an Incomplete Preference Relation. Journal of Economic Theory 104: 429–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, Derek. 1982. Personal Identity and Rationality. Synthese 53: 227–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, Derek. 2012. We Are Not Human Beings. Philosophy 87: 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattanaik, Prasanta K. 1970. On Social Choice with Quasi-Transitive Individual Preferences. Journal of Economic Theory 2: 267–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2001. Deliberative Democracy, the Discursive Dilemma, and Republican Theory. Noûs 35: 268–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plott, Charles R., James T. Little, and Robert P. Parks. 1975. Individual Choice When Objects Have “Ordinal” Properties. The Review of Economic Studies 42: 403–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raymond, Martin, and John Barresi, eds. 2003. Personal Identity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 1969. Quasi-Transitivity, Rational Choice and Collective Decisions. Revue of Economic Studies 36: 381–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 1970. Collective Choice and Social Welfare. Cambridge: Holden Day.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 1973. Behaviour and the Concept of Preference. Economica 40: 241–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 1974. Choice Ordering and Morality. In Practical Reason, ed. Stephan Körner. Oxford: Blackwell; Reprinted in Choice, Welfare and Measurement, ed. Amartya K. Sen, 74–83, 1982. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 1977. Rational Fools. Philosophy and Public Affairs 6: 317–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 1985. Commodities and Capabilities. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 1986a. Foundations of Social Choice Theory: An Epilogue. In Foundations of Social Choice Theory, ed. Jon Elster, and Aanund Hylland, 213–248. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 1986b. Social Choice Theory. In Handbook of Mathematical Economics, ed. Kenneth J. Arrow, and Michael D. Intriligator, Vol 3, 1073–1181. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 1997. Maximization and the Act of Choice. Econometrica 65: 745–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 2002. Rationality and Freedom. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 2004. Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice. Synthese 140: 43–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. 2006. Identity and Violence. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Styron, William. 1979. Sophie’s Choice. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thumma, Scott. 1991. Negotiating a Religious Identity: The Case of the Gay Evangelical. Sociological Analysis 52: 333–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. David. 1992. What Happens When Someone Acts? Mind 101: 461–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Gary. 1973. Free Agency. The Journal of Philosophy 72: 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weymark, John. 1984. Arrow’s Theorem with Social Quasi-Orderings. Public Choice 42: 235–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature B.V.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Binder, C. (2019). Plural Identities and Preference Formation. In: Agency, Freedom and Choice. Theory and Decision Library A:, vol 53. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-1615-2_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics