Skip to main content

Against the Drug Cure Model: Addiction, Identity, and Pharmaceuticals

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophical Issues in Pharmaceutics

Part of the book series: Philosophy and Medicine ((PHME,volume 122))

Abstract

Recent advances in brain imaging methods as well as increased sophistication in neuroscientific modeling of the brain’s reward systems have facilitated the study of neural mechanisms associated with addiction such as processes associated with motivation, decision-making, pleasure seeking, and inhibitory control. These scientific activities have increased optimism that the neurological underpinnings of addiction will be delineated, and that pharmaceuticals that target and change these mechanisms will by themselves facilitate early intervention and even full recovery. In this paper, we argue that it is misguided to construe addiction as just or primarily a brain chemistry problem, which can be adequately treated by pharmaceutical interventions alone.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    A sound theory of pharmaceuticals for addiction’s substrates must resist falling prey to what may be called the pharmaceutical temptation of the one over the many, which is a variety of monocausal thinking. The neural-causal etiology of addiction is not some one single personal subsystem; for example, it is not a dictatorship of the neural reward system. The best hope for an addict may sometimes be to combine psychotherapies with complements of drugs. But treatment, drugs used or not used, is enfeebled without appreciating that addicts are persons and addiction is a way of being in the world.

  2. 2.

    It is worth noting the distinction between multiplex self and multitudinous self. The multiplex self, a concept introduced by Flanagan, explains what the personal identity of those with typical cognition consists in. It refers to persons playing multiple roles simultaneously; i.e., the self is multiplex because the person represents and exhibits different parts of themselves to different audiences in different environments. For instance, “my philosopher self, my baseball-coach self, my religious self, my parental self—are played for different audiences. Different audiences see who we are differently” (Flanagan 1996: 71). Suggesting that the self is multiplex means that identity exists despite chronic transformations and synchronic conflicts between these different facets of a person, since there is a narrative connectedness between them. This narrative connectedness is due to the authorial work of the agent, who tells the story of her life and thus holds different strains together. If this unifying authorship falls apart, we end up with atypical cognition: we no longer deal with a multiplex self, but rather with multiple selves. The concept of multitudinous self, introduced by Tekin, on the other hand, considers the self to be complex matrix, individuated and constituted by five dimensions: ecological, interpersonal, temporal, private, and conceptual (following the Neisserian selves). Unlike the multiplex self, multitudinous self considers psychopathology or atypical cognition to be a possible feature of the self. Multiplex self, in so far as it is a conceptual representation of the self to the self, and others, can be situated within the conceptual dimension of the multitudinous self. The model of multitudinous self aims to (i) get at the complexity of “real people,” (ii) provide opportunities for scientists to use abstractions and idealizations and study it scientifically, and (iii) encourage a wholesome approach to psychopathology without sidestepping the complexity of persons. The inspiration for the name of this model is the poem “Song of Myself” by Walt Whitman, in which he proclaims, “Do I contradict myself? Very well, then, I contradict myself; (I am large—I contain multitudes).” Special thanks to Flanagan, who steered Tekin in the direction of these lines, hence the word “multitudinous.”

References

  • Bentall, R. 2009. Doctoring the Mind: Is Current Treatment of Mental Illness Really Any Good? New York: New York University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bowlby, J. 1969. Attachment and Loss. London: Hogarth Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deigh, J. 2010. An Introduction to Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown, and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. 1991. Varieties of Moral Personality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Self Expressions: Mind, Morals, and the Meaning of Life (Philosophy of Mind). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013a. The Shame of Addiction. Frontiers in Psychiatry 4(120): 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013b. Identity and Addiction: What Alcoholic Memoirs Teach. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, ed. K.W.M. Fulford et al., 865–888. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogel, A. 1993. Developing Through Relationships: Origins of Communication, Self, and Culture. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frances, A. 2013. Saving Normal. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gastfriend, D.R. 2005. Physician Substance Abuse and Recovery: What Does It Mean for Physicians and Everyone Else. Journal of the American Medical Association 293: 1513–1515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, G. 2013. The Disordered Mind: Philosophy of Mind and Mental Illness. 2nd ed. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. in press. The Abraham Dilemma: A Divine Delusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jopling, D. 1997. A ‘Self’ of Selves. In The Conceptual Self in Context, ed. U. Neisser et al., 249–268. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Self-Knowledge and the Self. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knapp, C. 1997. Drinking: A Love Story. New York: Dial Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. 1988. Five Kinds of Self-Knowledge. Philosophical Psychology 1: 35–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K., and K. Tabb. in press. Hempel as a Critic of Bridgman’s Operationalism: Lessons for Psychiatry from the History of Science (a Response to Bovet and Parnas). In Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry III, eds. Kendler, K.S., et al. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Chapter 24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, D. 1993. The Role of Feelings for an Interpersonal Self. In The Perceived Self: Ecological and Interpersonal Sources of Self-Knowledge, ed. U. Neisser, 205–215. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tekin, Ş. 2011. Self-concept through a Diagnostic Looking Glass: Narrative and Mental Disorder. Philosophical Psychology 24(3): 357–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013a. How Does the Self Adjudicate Narratives? Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 20(1): 25–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013b. “Will I be Pretty, Will I be Rich?” The Missing Self in Antidepressant 682 Commercials. The American Journal of Bioethics 13(05): 19–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014a. Self-Insight in the Time of Mood Disorders: After the Diagnosis, Beyond the Treatment. Philosophy, Psychiatry, Psychology 21(2): 139–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014b. The Missing Self in Hacking’s Looping Effects. In Classifying Psychopathology: Mental Kinds and Natural Kinds, ed. Kincaid et al., 227–256. Cambridge, MA: MIT University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014c. Psychiatric Taxonomy: At the Crossroads of Science and Ethics. Journal of Medical Ethics 40: 513–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Against Hyponarrating Grief: Incompatible Research and Treatment Interests in the DSM-5. In The DSM-5 in Perspective, History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, ed. S. Singy et al. Dordrecht: Springer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. 1980. The Foundations of Intersubjectivity: Development of Interpersonal and Cooperative Understanding in Infants. In The Social Foundations of Language and Thought: Essays in Honor of J. S. Bruner, ed. D. Olson, 316–342. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, R. 2006. Theory of Addiction. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkes, K. 1988. Real People. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Şerife Tekin .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Tekin, Ş., Flanagan, O., Graham, G. (2017). Against the Drug Cure Model: Addiction, Identity, and Pharmaceuticals. In: Ho, D. (eds) Philosophical Issues in Pharmaceutics. Philosophy and Medicine, vol 122. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-0979-6_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics