Skip to main content

Historical Contingency and the Explanation of Evolutionary Trends

  • Chapter
Explanation in Biology

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 11))

Abstract

One “big question” of macroevolutionary theory is the degree to which evolutionary history is contingent. A second “big question” is whether particular large-scale evolutionary trends, such as size increase or complexity increase, are passive or driven. Showing that a trend is passive or driven is a way of explaining it. These two “big questions” are related in both a superficial and a deep way. Superficially, defending historical contingency and showing that major trends are passive are two complementary ways of downplaying the importance of natural selection in evolutionary history. A passive trend is one that’s not explained by selection. In order to appreciate the deeper connection between the two issues, it is necessary to distinguish different senses of contingency (especially sensitivity to initial conditions vs. unbiased sorting). It’s plausible that passive trends are generally due to unbiased sorting processes. Serendipitously, thinking of contingency as unbiased sorting also helps to clarify its relationship to species selection, which some think of as biased sorting. Macroevolutionary theory thus turns out to have considerable unity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Alroy, J. (1998). Cope’s rule and the dynamics of body mass evolution in North American fossil mammals. Science, 280, 731–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. (1995). The evolutionary contingency thesis. In G. Wolters & J. Lennox (Eds.), Concepts, theories, and rationality in the biological sciences (pp. 45–81). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. (1997). Why do biologists argue like they do? Philosophy of Science, 64(4 supp), S432–S443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. (2006). Replaying life’s tape. Journal of Philosophy, 103(7), 336–362.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Menahem, Y. (1997). Historical contingency. Ratio, 10, 99–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calcott, B., & Sterelny, K. (Eds.). (2011). The major transitions in evolution revisited. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. (2001). Historical science, experimental science, and the scientific method. Geology, 29, 987–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. (2002). Methodological and epistemic differences between historical and experimental science. Philosophy of Science, 69, 474–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. (2011). Prediction and explanation in historical natural science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(3), 551–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conway Morris, S. (2003a). Life’s solution: Inevitable humans in a lonely universe. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Conway Morris, S. (Ed.). (2003b). The deep structure of biology: Is convergence sufficiently ubiquitous to give a directional signal. West Conshohocken: Templeton Foundation Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DesJardins, E. (2011). Historicity and experimental evolution. Biology and Philosophy, 26, 339–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallie, W. B. (1959). Explanations in history and the genetic sciences. In P. Gardiner (Ed.), Theories of history (pp. 386–402). Glencoe: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1989). Wonderful life: The Burgess shale and the nature of history. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1993). Eight little piggies. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1996). Full house: The spread of excellence from Plato to Darwin. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1997). Cope’s rule as psychological artefact. Nature, 385(6613), 199–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (2002). The structure of evolutionary theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 205, 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grantham, T. (1999). Explanatory pluralism in paleobiology. Philosophy of Science, 66(supp), S223–S 236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harries, P. J., & Knorr, P. O. (2009). What does the “Lilliput effect” mean? Paleogeography, Paleoclimatology, Paleoecology, 284, 4–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hone, D. W. E., & Benton, M. J. (2005). The evolution of large size: How does Cope’s rule work? Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 20(1), 4–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1975). Central subjects and historical narratives. History and Theory, 14(3), 253–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Inkpen, R., & Turner, D. (2012). The topography of historical contingency. Journal of the Philosophy of History, 6, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonski, D. (1997). Body size evolution in cretaceous mollusks and the status of Cope’s rule. Nature, 385, 250–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffares, B. (2008). Testing times: Regularities in the historical sciences. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 39, 469–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenski, R. E., & Travisano, M. (1994). Dynamics of adaptation and diversification: A 10,000 generation experiment with bacterial populations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 91, 6808–6814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M., & Ariew, A. (2002). Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. The Journal of Philosophy, 99(2), 55–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., & Szathmary, E. (1995). The major transitions in evolution. Oxford: W.H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • McShea, D. W. (1994). Mechanisms of large-scale evolutionary trends. Evolution, 48, 1747–1763.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McShea, D. W. (1998). Possible largest-scale trends in organismal evolution: Eight ‘live hypotheses’. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 29, 293–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McShea, D. W. (2005). The evolution of complexity without natural selection: A possible large-scale trend of the fourth kind. Paleobiology, 31(supp), 146–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McShea, D. W., & Brandon, R. N. (2010). Biology’s first law. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein, R. (2000). Chance and macroevolution. Philosophy of Science, 67(4), 603–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radick, G. (2005). Other histories, other biologies. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 80(56), 21–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raup, D. M., & Gould, S. J. (1974). Stochastic simulation and the evolution of morphology—towards a nomothetic paleontology. Systematic Zoology, 23, 305–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raup, D. M., Gould, S. J., Schopf, T. J. M., & Simberloff, D. (1973). Stochastic models of phylogeny and the evolution of diversity. Journal of Geology, 81, 525–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A., & McShea, D. W. (2007). Philosophy of biology: A contemporary introduction. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sepkoski, D. (2012). Rereading the fossil record: The growth of paleontology as an evolutionary discipline. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1988). Reconstructing the past: Parsimony, evolution, and inference. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, S. (1975). A theory of evolution above the species level. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 72(2), 646–650.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (1996). Explanatory pluralism in evolutionary biology. Biology and Philosophy, 11, 193–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2005). Another view of life. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 585–593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travisano, M., Mangold, J. A., Bennett, A. F., & Lenski, R. E. (1995). Experimental tests of the roles of adaptation, chance, and history in evolution. Science, 27(5194), 87–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, A. (2004). Our knowledge of the past: A philosophy of historiography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. (2007). Making prehistory: Historical science and the scientific realism debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. (2009). How much can we know about the causes of evolutionary trends? Biology and Philosophy, 24, 341–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. (2010). Gould’s replay revisited. Biology and Philosophy, 26, 65–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. (2011). Paleontology: A philosophical introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M., Ariew, A., & Lewens, T. (2002). The trials of life: Natural selection and random drift. Philosophy of Science, 69(3), 452–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, S. C. (2001). Quantifying passive and driven large-scale evolutionary trends. Evolution, 55(5), 849–858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I shared earlier versions of this paper at the PSA meeting in San Diego in November, 2012, and at the AAAS meeting in Boston in February, 2013. Thanks to those audiences and especially to John Beatty, Eric DesJardins, Marc Ereshefsky, and David Sepkoski, for helpful feedback. I am grateful to the editors of this volume, Christophe Malaterre and Pierre-Alain Braillard, for their detailed comments on an earlier draft and their help improving the paper. The paper also benefitted from feedback from two anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Derek Turner .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Turner, D. (2015). Historical Contingency and the Explanation of Evolutionary Trends. In: Explanation in Biology. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 11. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9822-8_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics