Skip to main content

Prospect and Limits of Explaining Biological Systems in Engineering Terms

  • Chapter
Explanation in Biology

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 11))

Abstract

Systems biology represents an effort to develop new modelling approaches in molecular and cell biology, drawing inspiration from disciplines like physics, computer sciences and engineering. In particular, many scientists have called for a transfer of methods, models and concepts from engineering in order to analyze and explain biological systems in all their complexity. In this paper, I examine how such transfer can contribute to systems biology explanatory project. Model building in the context of post-genomic biology raises a number of difficult challenges, mainly due to the complexity of the processes studied and their intricate dynamical features. Engineering methods can be used to efficiently analyze quantitative data about systems behaviour and use them to build mathematical dynamical models, in a way that goes beyond classical mechanistic approaches. More generally, engineering has suggested adopting a modular framework, as a general approach of decomposition and explanation based on analogies between biological and engineered systems, which promises to identify intelligible principles in the complex organization of molecular networks. I discuss the nature of this explanatory framework and on what assumptions it rests.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    These issues are discussed in this volume by Baetu (2015), Breidenmoser and Wolkenhauer (2015), Brigandt (2015), Issad and Malaterre (2015), and Zednik (2015).

  2. 2.

    Note that I do not offer an explication of the notion of explanation. This might sound problematic in a volume about explanation, however instead of developing a general account of explanation in biology, I think that it is more interesting to analyze the various models that are considered as explanatory and how they relate to each other. Hence the analysis offered in this chapter should bring useful elements for an understanding of how engineering contributes to modify and enrich explanatory models in biology, even without a general account of what it means to explain.

  3. 3.

    For a discussion of the challenges and methods of reverse engineering, see for example Kell and Knowles 2006, Chapter 11.

  4. 4.

    Some of the modelling methods used in engineering are also used in other domains and are indeed very general, especially the whole framework of dynamic systems theory. But the point is that many of these methods, tough they are not purely belonging to engineering, have been developed and put to use by engineers in the study and design of complex systems.

  5. 5.

    What I mean by these expressions will become clear in the following discussion.

  6. 6.

    A word of caution: even if one restricts oneself to SB, the concept of module can be differently understood. The following analysis does not pretend to capture all of these uses and dimensions. Everyone in the field certainly does not hold some of the views and other modular approaches will not be discussed here.

  7. 7.

    One might object that motifs are different from modules, but the explanatory goal is the same: model a small sub-system and capture its essential dynamical properties.

  8. 8.

    One might object that these are biological functions. However, the focus is for example on how a signal is transformed, regardless of the nature of the signal or its biological function. Of course, the goal is always to explain biological function, but I maintain that often in this kind of approach biological function becomes less important.

  9. 9.

    When talking about robustness, it is important to keep in mind that it is meaningless if not defined in terms of specific properties of the systems that are robust to specific changes (internal or external). A feature of a given mechanism can be robust to one perturbation and very sensitive to a different one. Hence we must say that functional property P is robust to perturbation X.

  10. 10.

    For one of the first philosophical discussions of the need for different types of decomposition in biology, see (Wimsatt 1974).

References

  • Alon, U. (2006). An introduction to systems biology: Design principles of biological circuits. Boca Raton: Chapman & Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baetu, T. (2015). From mechanisms to mathematical models and back to mechanisms: Quantitative mechanistic explanations. In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 345–363). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brazhnik, P., Fuente, A., & Mendes, P. (2002). Gene networks: How to put the function in genomics. Trends in Biotechnology, 20(11), 467–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breidenmoser, T., & Wolkenhauer, O. (2015). Explanation and organizing principles in systems biology. In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 249–264). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2015). Evolutionary developmental biology and the limits of philosophical accounts of mechanistic explanation. In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 135–173). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut, W., & Rasskin-Gutman, D. (Eds.). (2005). Modularity: Understanding the development and evolution of natural complex systems. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, J. M., & Doyle, J. C. (2002). Complexity and robustness. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 99(90001), 2538–2545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2006). When mechanistic models explain. Synthese, 153, 355–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csete, M. E., & Doyle, J. C. (2002). Reverse engineering of biological complexity. Science, 295, 1664–1669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Haeseleer, P., Liang, S., & Somogyi, R. (2000). Genetic network inference: From co-expression clustering to reverse engineering. Bioinformatics, 16, 707–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Del Vecchio, D., Ninfa, A. J., & Sontag, E. D. (2008). Modular cell biology: Retroactivity and insulation. Molecular Systems Biology, 4, 16110.

    Google Scholar 

  • El-Samad, H., et al. (2005). Surviving heat shock: Control strategies for robustness and performance. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 102, 2736–2741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, F. (2015). The relevance of irrelevance: Explanation in systems biology. In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 175–198). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunawan, R., Gadkar, K. G., & Doyle, F. J. (2006). Methods to identify cellular architecture and dynamics from experimental data. In Z. Szallasi, J. Stelling, & V. Periwal (Eds.), Systems modeling in cell biology. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartwell, L. H., et al. (1999). From molecular to modular cell biology. Nature, 402, C47–C52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ihmels, J., et al. (2002). Revealing modular organization in the yeast transcriptional network. Nature Genetics, 31, 370–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • Issad, T., & Malaterre, C. (2015). Are dynamic mechanistic explanations still mechanistic? In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 265–292). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kell, D. B., & Knowles, J. D. (2006). The role of modeling in systems biology. In Z. Szallasi, J. Stelling, & V. Periwal (Eds.), Systems modeling in cellular biology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (2003). Making sense of life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitano, H. (2004). Biological robustness. Nature Review Genetics, 5, 826–837.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kremling, A., & Saez-Rodriguez, J. (2007). Systems biology – An engineering perspective. Journal of Biotechnology, 129(2), 329–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauffenburger, D. A. (2000). Cell signaling pathways as control modules: Complexity for simplicity? Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 97, 5031–5033.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lazebnik, Y. (2002). Can a biologists fix a radio? – Or what I learned while studying apoptosis. Cancer Cell, 2, 179–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipan, O. (2008). Systems biology. Enlightening rhythms. Science, 319(5862), 417–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mangan, S., & Alon, U. (2003). Structure and function of the feed-forward loop network motif. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 100, 11980–11985.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mettetal, J. T., et al. (2008). The frequency dependence of osmo-adaptation in Saccharomyces cerevisiae. Science, 319, 482–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. (2005). Modularity: More than a buzzword? Biological Theory, 1(1), 98–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morohashi, et al. (2002). Robustness as a measure of plausibility in models of biochemical networks. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 216, 19–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rao, C. V., & Arkin, A. P. (2001). Control motifs for intracellular regulatory networks. Annual Review of Biomedical Engineering, 3, 391–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raser, J. M., & O’Shea, E. K. (2005). Noise in gene expression: Origins, consequences, and control. Science, 309, 2010–2013.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1972). Some systems theoretical problems in biology. In E. Lazlo (Ed.), The relevance of general systems theory. New York: George Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, G., & Wagner, G. P. (Eds.). (2004). Modularity in development and evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segal, E., et al. (2003). Module networks: Identifying regulatory modules and their condition-specific regulators from gene expression data. Nature Genetics, 34(2), 166–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1996 [1969]). The sciences of the artificial (3rd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stelling, J., et al. (2004). Robustness of cellular functions. Cell, 118, 675–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szalli, Z., et al. (2006). On modules and modularity. In Z. Szallasi, J. Stelling, & V. Periwal (Eds.), System modeling in cellular biology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tomlin, C. J., & Axelrod, J. D. (2005). Understanding biology by reverse engineering the control. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 102, 4219–4220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tyson, J. J., et al. (2003). Sniffers, buzzers, toggles and blinkers. Current Opinion in Cell Biology, 15(2), 221–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Dassow, G., & Meir, E. (2004). Exploring modularity with dynamical models of gene networks. In G. Schlosser & G. P. Wagner (Eds.), Modularity in development and evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Dassow, G., et al. (2000). The segment polarity network is a robust developmental module. Nature, 406, 188–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, A. (2005). Robustness and evolvability in living systems. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1974). Complexity and organization. In K. F. Schaffner & R. S. Cohen (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1972 meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (pp. 67–86). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther, R. G. (2001). Varieties of modules: Kinds, levels, origins, and behaviors. Journal of Experimental Zoology, 291, 116–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, D., & Arkin, A. (2003). Motifs, modules, and games. Current Opinion in Microbiology, 6, 125–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolkenhauer, O. (2006). Engineering approaches: What can we learn from it in systems biology? In R. van Driel (Ed.), Systems biology: A grand challenge for Europe European science foundation forward look report. Strasbourg: European Science Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yildirim, M. A., & Vidal, M. (2008). Systems engineering to systems biology. Molecular Systems Biology, 4, 185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zednik, C. (2015). Heuristics, descriptions, and the scope of mechanistic explanation. In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 295–317). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The ideas discussed in this paper have been presented at different occasions, mainly at the 2013 ISHPSSB meeting in Montpellier and at the IHPST Paris-CAPE Kyoto philosophy of biology workshop. I would like to thank the audiences for useful discussions. An earlier version of this paper also benefited from comments from Christophe Malaterre, as well from two anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierre-Alain Braillard .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Braillard, PA. (2015). Prospect and Limits of Explaining Biological Systems in Engineering Terms. In: Explanation in Biology. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 11. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9822-8_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics