Skip to main content

Truth as Composite Correspondence

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Unifying the Philosophy of Truth

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 36))

Abstract

Is a substantive standard of truth for theories of the world by and for humans possible? What kind of standard would that be? How intricate would it be? How unified would it be? How would it work in “problematic” fields of truth like mathematics? The paper offers an answer to these questions in the form of a “composite” correspondence theory of truth. By allowing variations in the way truths in different branches of knowledge correspond to reality the theory succeeds in rendering correspondence universal, and by investigating, rather than taking as given, the structure of the correspondence relation in various fields of knowledge, it makes a substantive account of correspondence possible. In particular, the paper delineates a “composite” type of correspondence applicable to mathematics, traces its roots in views of other philosophers, and shows how it solves well-known problems in the philosophy of mathematics, due to Benacerraf and others.

Earlier versions of this paper was presented at the Truth at Work Conference in Paris, 2011 and at the philosophy colloquium at UC Santa Barbara the same year. I would like to thank the audiences at both events for very constructive comments. This paper continues my earlier work on truth, knowledge, and logic, e.g., Sher (2004, 2010, 2011).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The compromise concerning unity results from their willingness to assign altogether different standards of truth—e.g., correspondence vs. coherence standards—to different disciplines. The compromise concerning the connection between truth and reality arises from their willingness to assign a non-correspondence standard of truth to allegedly “problematic” disciplines. (It’s important to note, however, that neither Wright nor Lynch is in principle averse to assigning a correspondence standard to any discipline).

  2. 2.

    Indeed, given that we have more options in treating the simple cases than the complex cases, combinatorically it makes sense to start with the latter.

  3. 3.

    It should be noted, though, that Horgan approaches truth from a somewhat different direction than we do. In particular, Horgan is interested in solving the problem of vagueness while we are interested in solving the epistemic problem of truth. These problems are not completely disconnected, but the difference is in certain ways insignificant.

  4. 4.

    A universe is a non-empty set of individuals. The structures <U, P> and <U’,P’> are isomorphic iff there is a 1-1 and onto function f from U to U’ such that P’ is the image of P in U’ under f.

  5. 5.

    This problem is raised by nominalists of various stripes (e.g., Goodman and Quine 1947), mathematical finitists, supporters of V = L, and others who feel uncomfortable with the huge ontology of contemporary (classical) set-theory. Here I focus on the issue of size.

  6. 6.

    For further discussion of the philosophical ramifications of invariance, see Sher (1999a, 2008).

  7. 7.

    The issue of algebraic vs. non-algebraic mathematical theories is discussed in, e.g., Shapiro (1997).

  8. 8.

    This account (and explanation) applies smoothly to geometry, but Aristotle uses a somewhat different (and arguably weaker) account for arithmetic. For us, post-Fregean philosophers, however, it’s natural to extend Aristotle’s account of geometry to arithmetic, by viewing numbers as representing cardinality properties of physical objects.

  9. 9.

    For a discussion of this point, though not as it relates to Aristotle, see Sher (2010).

  10. 10.

    This is a significant issue. For discussion see Sher (1999b, 2010).

  11. 11.

    This will be briefly discussed in the next section. See references there.

  12. 12.

    This approach is argued for and explained in Sher (1998–9, 2004).

  13. 13.

    An earlier version, directed as modal fictionalism, is due to Rosen (1990).

  14. 14.

    Our speech is engaged when we speak from within a given game, disengaged when we speak from outside it.

  15. 15.

    For further discussion of our holistic, Neurathian conception of knowledge see Sher (1999b, 2010).

  16. 16.

    The logical truth “Pa ∨ ~ Pa” is an image of the mathematical truth that a is in the union of P and its complement (in the given universe), the logical inference “Pa∨Qa, ~ Pa; therefore Qa” is the image of the mathematical inference that if a is in the union of P and Q, yet is not in P, then it is in Q, and so on.

  17. 17.

    This correspondence would be properly composite (i.e., will involve more than one step) if logical laws are construed as directly concerning linguistic entities and indirectly the world.

  18. 18.

    For a detailed discussion of this approach to logic and mathematics from the perspective of logic, see, e.g., Sher (1996, 1999a, 2008).

References

  • Benacerraf, P. (1965). What numbers could not be. Philosophical Review, 74, 47–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1973). Mathematical truth. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 661–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1989). Realism, mathematics & modality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1884). The foundations of arithmetic: A logico-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number (trans: J. L. Austin). Evanston: Northwestern. (1968).

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1918). Thoughts. In P. T. Geach (Ed.), Logical investigations (trans: P. T. Geach & R. H. Stoothoff) (pp. 1–30). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N., & Quine W. V. (1947). Steps toward a constructive nominalism. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 12, 105–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (2001). Contextual semantics & metaphysical realism: Truth as indirect correspondence. In M. Lynch (Ed.), The nature of truth: Classic & contemporary perspectives (pp. 67–95). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lear, J. (1982). Aristotle philosophy of mathematics. Philosophical Review, 91, 161–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. (2001). Realism and the correspondence theory: Introduction. In M. Lynch (Ed.), The nature of truth: Classic & contemporary perspectives (pp. 7–15). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. (2009). Truth as one & many. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1955). Posits & reality . The ways of paradox and other essays (pp. 246–254). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (1976). (Revised and Enlarged Ed.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (1990). Modal fictionalism. Mind, 99, 327–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of mathematics: Structure & ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (1991). The bounds of logic: A generalized viewpoint. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (1996). Did tarski commit ‘tarski’s fallacy’? Journal of Symbolic Logic, 61, 653–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (1998–9). On the possibility of a substantive theory of truth. Synthese, 117, 133–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (1999a). Is logic a theory of the obvious? European Review of Philosophy, 4, 207–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (1999b). Is there a place for philosophy in quine’s theory? Journal of Philosophy, 96, 491–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2004). In search of a substantive theory of truth. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 5–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2008). Tarski’s thesis. In D. Patterson (Ed.), New essays on tarski and philosophy (pp. 300–339). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2010). Epistemic friction: Reflections on knowledge, truth, and logic. Erkenntnis, 72, 151–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2011). Is logic in the mind or in the world? Synthese, 181, 353–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications in Pure & Applied Mathematics, 13, 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1992). Truth and objectivity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2001). Go figure: A path through fictionalism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 25, 72–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gila Sher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sher, G. (2015). Truth as Composite Correspondence. In: Achourioti, T., Galinon, H., Martínez Fernández, J., Fujimoto, K. (eds) Unifying the Philosophy of Truth. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 36. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9673-6_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics