Skip to main content

Vagueness, Truth and Permissive Consequence

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Unifying the Philosophy of Truth

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 36))

Abstract

We say that a sentence A is a permissive consequence of a set of premises Γ whenever, if all the premises of Γ hold up to some standard, then A holds to some weaker standard. In this paper, we focus on a three-valued version of this notion, which we call strict-to-tolerant consequence, and discuss its fruitfulness toward a unified treatment of the paradoxes of vagueness and self-referential truth. For vagueness, st-consequence supports the principle of tolerance; for truth, it supports the requisit of transparency. Permissive consequence is non-transitive, however, but this feature is argued to be an essential component to the understanding of paradoxical reasoning in cases involving vagueness or self-reference.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    (Smith 2008), for instance, defines a notion of permissive consequence for fuzzy logic with continuum many truth values linearly ordered (the real interval [0,1]), whereby a sentence A is said to follow from a set of premises Γ provided in all models in which all formulae in Γ have value strictly greater than half, A gets a value greater or equal than 1/2. This notion of permissive consequence, as fine-grained though it appears, can in fact be shown to be representable without loss of generality in a three-valued framework, and indeed, both Smith’s notion and its three-valued version coincide with classical consequence for first-order logic. We refer to (Cobreros et al. Ms.) for details and more ample discussion of this point.

  2. 2.

    We state the definition in terms of a multi-premise and multi-conclusion setting, although, for most of the applications we are interested in here, we can limit our perspective to the multi-premise-single-conclusion case.

  3. 3.

    Malinowski’s notion of q-consequence is defined exactly in terms of the basic attitudes of acceptance and rejection. A sentence A is a q-consequence of a set of premises Γ whenever A is accepted when all of the premises in Γ are not rejected.

  4. 4.

    The generalization to n-ary predicates presents no special difficulty, and only involves the definition of appropriate similarity relations between n-tuples.

  5. 5.

    For more rigor, we might have chosen to break the proviso 21.1 into two separate constraints: first, the crispness constraint that \(M\models^{s} aI_{P}b\) iff \(M\models^{t} aI_{P}b\) (see (Cobreros et al. 2012b)), and secondly, the closeness constraint proper that if \(M\models^{s/t} aI_{P}b\), then \(| I(Pa)-I(Pb)|<1\) (not assuming the “only if” part). That way of doing things actually appears preferable to us in general, but we collapse both constraints in 21.1 for the sake of simplicity.

  6. 6.

    Type-free treatments of the Liar purporting to maintain classical logic ought to be mentioned too. See in particular the contextualist accounts of (Parsons 1974) and (Glanzberg 2004), who both argue that the Liar rests on a phenomenon of variable quantifier domain restriction.

  7. 7.

    We are indebted to an anonymous reviewer for this important clarification. As pointed out by the reviewer, in Kripke’s construction the minimal fixed point V for the supervaluation schema satisfies the fixed point property, but not transparency, since as a consequence of the lack of value-functionality in the supervaluation schema, \(V(\lambda \vee{T}{\langle{\lambda}\rangle})=V(\neg{T}{\langle{\lambda}\rangle} \vee{T}{\langle{\lambda}\rangle})=1\), but \(V({T}{\langle{\lambda}\rangle} \vee{T}{\langle{\lambda}\rangle})=1/2\). Conversely, a transparent theory of truth may fail identity, for example if you start from a Kripke-Kleene model M and generate a new model \(M'\) that assigns to each sentence A the pair \(<M(A), A>\) as a value, and then simply ignore the second coordinate of its values when defining validity. This sort of model will yield the same logic as the original models, but without ever assigning the same value to any two distinct sentences, so it will exhibit transparency without identity.

  8. 8.

    (Smith 2008) presents closeness as an explicit weakening of tolerance in his fuzzy approach, and means to endorse closeness without endorsing tolerance. See (Cobreros et al. (Ms.)) however for a more thorough discussion of the status of both principles in relation to Smith’s notion of consequence. Conversely, the theory of vagueness presented in (Cobreros et al. 2012b), which involves the notion of classical extension for vague predicates, is one in which tolerance is st-valid, but without involving the notion of closeness in truth values. Tolerance t-holds in all models despite the existence of elements a and b for which \(aI_{P}b\) holds (strictly or tolerantly), but such that \(|I(Pa)-I(Pb)|=1\) in the two-valued models used.

  9. 9.

    See also (Cobreros et al. 2013) for a discussion of structural motivations for the admission of non-transitive consequence.

  10. 10.

    On the comparison between norms of assertion with regard to theories of truth, see especially (Wintein 2012). Chapter 7 of (Wintein 2012), in particular, presents a theory of truth based on the strict-tolerant distinction, but taking a different perspective on Kripke-Kleene models for truth as well as on assertibility proper.

  11. 11.

    See, again, (Zardini 2008).

  12. 12.

    Our view on this should be compared to Priest’s original view on the status of modus ponens, a rule that is not LP-valid, but that Priest calls a “quasi-validity”, still applicable to sentences that are not paradoxical. In our system, modus ponens is a validity, but wherever Priest talks of quasi-validities that are lost in relation to the conditional, we can speak of corresponding classical metainferences that are lost for consequence in the vicinity of paradoxes.

  13. 13.

    We are indebted to an anonymous reviewer for drawing attention to this point.

  14. 14.

    See (Wright 1992), (Fara 2003), (Cobreros 2011) on gap principles, and (Egré 2011) and (van Rooij 2012) on the link between tolerance in the strict-tolerant framework and gap principles.

  15. 15.

    Rogers’ emphasis on the use of partial, as opposed to total, functions as a way of blocking diagonalization arguments bears some analogy with the idea of limiting the expressiveness of our language to block the strengthened Liar.

  16. 16.

    See (Ripley 2013a) for an application of this strategy to deal with a particular version of higher-order vagueness.

References

  • Bennett, B. (1998). Modal semantics for knowledge bases dealing with vague concepts. In A. G. Cohn, L. Schubert, & S. Shapiro (Eds.), Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning: Proceedings of the 6th International Conference (KR-98), Morgan Kaufman, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobreros, P. (2011). Supervaluationism and Fara’s argument concerning higher-order vagueness. In P. Egré & N. Klinedinst (eds.), Vagueness and language use (pp. 207–221).

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2012a). Tolerance and mixed consequence in the s’valuationist setting. Studia Logica, 100(4):855–877.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2012b). Tolerant, classical, strict. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41(2), 347–385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (Ms). Tolerance and Degrees of Truth. Manuscript, in progress (of a paper presented at Cerisy 2011 and ESSLLI 2012).

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2013). Reaching transparent truth. Mind. 122(488):841–866.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2009). Vagueness and truth. In H. Dyke (ed.), From truth to reality: New essays in logic and metaphysics (pp. 29–40). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, R. (2009). What is a truth value and how many are there? Studia Logica, 92(2), 183–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egré, P. (2011). Perceptual ambiguity and the sorites. In R. Nouwen, R. van Rooij, U. Sauerland, & H.-C. Schmitz (eds.), Vagueness in communication (pp. 64–90). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fara, D. (2003). Gap principles, penumbral consequence, and infinitely higher-order vagueness. Liars and heaps: New essays on paradox (pp. 195–222) (Originally published under the name “Delia Graff”).

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2003). Semantic paradoxes and vagueness paradoxes. In J. Beall (ed.), Liars and heaps (pp. 262–311). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2008). Saving truth from paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankowski, S. (2004). Formalization of a plausible inference. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 33(1), 41–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glanzberg, M. (2004). A contextual-hierarchical approach to truth and the liar paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 33(1), 27–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyde, D. (1997). From heaps and gaps to heaps of gluts. Mind, 106,641–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kleene, S. (1952). Introduction to metamathematics. D. Van Nostrand Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kooi, B., & Tamminga, A. (2013). Three-valued logics in modal logic. Studia Logica, 101(5), 1061–1072.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1975). Outline of a theory of truth. The Journal of Philosophy, 72(19), 690–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1982). Logic for equivocators. Noûs, 16(3), 431–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malinowski, G. (1990). Q-consequence operation. Reports on mathematical logic, 24, 49–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGee, V. (1991). Truth, vagueness, and paradox: An essay on the logic of truth. Hackett Pub Co Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nait-Abdallah, A. (1995). The logic of partial information. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, C. (1974). The liar paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 3(4), 381–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (1979). Logic of paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 219–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (1984). Hyper-contradictions. Logique et Analyse, 27(107), 237–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2010). Inclosures, vagueness, and self-reference. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 51(1), 69–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raffman, D. (2014). Unruly words: A study of vague language. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ripley, D. (2012). Conservatively extending classical logic with a transparent truth predicate. Review of Symbolic Logic 5(2):354–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ripley, D. (2013a). Sorting out the sorites. In F. Berto, E. Mares, & K. Tanaka, (eds.), Paraconsistency: Logic and applications. Springer 329–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ripley, D. (2013b). Paradoxes and failures of cut. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91(1):139–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, H. (1987). Theory of recursive functions and effective computability. MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumfitt, I. (2000). “Yes and no”. Mind, 109(436), 781–823.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, P. (2010). Super liars. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 1(1), 1–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. J. J. (2008). Vagueness and degrees of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tappenden, J. (1993). The liar and sorites paradoxes: Toward a unified treatment. The Journal of Philosophy, 90(11), 551–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij, R. (2012). Vagueness, tolerance, and non-transitive entailment. In P. Cintula, C. Fermueller, L. Godo, & P. Hàjek (Eds), Understanding vagueness—Logical, philosophical and linguistic perspectives (pp. 205–221). King’s College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wintein, S. (2012). Playing with truth. PhD Thesis, Tilburg University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1976). Language-mastery and the sorites paradox. In G. Evans, & J. McDowell (Eds.), Truth and meaning: Essays in Semantics, pp. 223–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1992). Is higher order vagueness coherent? Analysis, 52(3), 129–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1995). The epistemic conception of vagueness. The Southern journal of philosophy, 33(S1), 133–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zardini, E. (2008). A model of tolerance. Studia Logica, 90, 337–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to two anonymous referees for detailed comments, and to the editors for their assistance in the preparation of this paper. We also thank audiences in Amsterdam, Barcelona and Paris. We thank the European Research Council under the European Community’s Seventh Framework Programme (FP7/2007-2013) / ERC grant agreement n 229 441-CCC, the ANR project BTAFDOC (“Beyond Truth and Falsity: Degrees of Confidence”), and the program “Non-Transitive Logics” (Ministerio de Economía y Competitividad, Government of Spain, FFI2013-46451-P). We also thank grants ANR-10-LABX-0087 IEC and ANR-10-IDEX-0001-02 PSL*.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul Egré .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., Rooij, R. (2015). Vagueness, Truth and Permissive Consequence. In: Achourioti, T., Galinon, H., Martínez Fernández, J., Fujimoto, K. (eds) Unifying the Philosophy of Truth. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 36. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9673-6_21

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics