Skip to main content

Truth, Signification and Paradox

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 36))

Abstract

Thomas Bradwardine’s solution to the semantic paradoxes, presented in his Insolubilia written in Oxford in the early 1320s, turns on two main principles: that a proposition is true only if things are wholly as it signifies; and that signification is closed under consequence. After exploring the background in Walter Burley’s account of the signification of propositions, I consider the extent to which Bradwardine’s theory is compatible with the compositional principles of the distribution of truth over conjunction, disjunction, negation and the conditional.

Presented at the Conference on ‘Truth at Work’, Paris 20–23 June 2011. This work is supported by Research Grant AH/F018398/1 (Foundations of Logical Consequence) from the Arts and Humanities Research Council, UK.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    (Raine 1843), p. xii: “Dubito certe annon in te solum cudatur proverbium Asinus ad lyram. At profecto tu non dignus es qui esses procurator in sophistarum scholis: sic enim insurgit quidam sophista contra Procuratorem; ‘Qui dicit te esse animal dicit verum; at qui dicit te esse asinum dicit te esse animal ergo, qui dicit te esse asinum dicit verum.’ ‘Concedo totum,’ inquit Procurator: ‘non ausus sum negare pro auribus.’ Videtis, itaque, Procurator fatetur se esse asinum per confessionem auricularem.” I am grateful to my colleague, Professor Sarah Broadie, for her help in trying to capture the subtlety of the original Latin in English. The proverb comes from Aesop’s Fables. ‘Auricular confession’ apparently means confession made vocally by the penitent to a priest, as distinct from silently addressed to God. Presumably there’s a supposed threat that if he says he’s not a donkey then they’ll make it true that he’s not a donkey by cutting off his (donkey’s) ears.

  2. 2.

    (Geulincx 1662) actually uses the example ‘Charles is now king of England’: see (Nuchelmans 1988, p. 269).

  3. 3.

    The Abstractiones are as yet unpublished; a preliminary edition can be found online at (Ricardus n.d.).

  4. 4.

    Burley’s treatise was edited in (Burley 1955), and translated into English in (Burley 2000). The counter-example also appears in the treatise on ‘Consequences’ of 1302 attributed to Burley and edited in (Green-Pedersen 1980, p. 113), but the later passage of the Shorter Treatise is little more than a verbatim repetition of the earlier text. The example is discussed, rather inconsequentially, in (Jacquette 2007a) (which is a shorter version of (Jacquette 2007b)).

  5. 5.

    (Burley 1955, p. 200 ff.): “Quidquid sequitur ad consequens, sequitur ad antecedens.”

  6. 6.

    (Burley 1955, p. 205), my own translation.

  7. 7.

    (Geulincx 1662, II.i.3.2; Land 1891, I p. 238). Cf. (Nuchelmans 1994, p. 94).

  8. 8.

    (Geulincx 1662, IV.ii.16.9-10) (Land 1891, I pp. 452–453).

  9. 9.

    “Cum superius sit dicere te esse animal quam dicere te esse asinum.”

  10. 10.

    “Et non ualet: te esse animal est uerum, ergo omnis dicens te esse animal dicit uerum; sed est fallacia figurae dictionis; commutatur enim unus modus supponendi in alium.”

  11. 11.

    See, e.g., (Conti 2011, § 4; Cesalli 2007, pp. 190 ff.).

  12. 12.

    (Brown 1973, § 1.03): “Oratio in mente componitur ex rebus patet per Commentatorem, VI Metaphysicae, in fine, qui dicit quod entia vera, cuiusmodi sunt propositiones, facta sunt ab intellectu quando dividit ea ab invicem vel componit ea ad invicem.”

  13. 13.

    See (Bradwardine 2010, ‘Introduction’ § 4).

  14. 14.

    \(p\to(q\to r)\) entails \((p{ \wedge} q)\to r\) (but not vice versa) in the logics of strict implication S2 (and stronger) and of relevant implication, R: on the latter, see, e.g., (Anderson and Belnap 1975, § 29.3.1, R30 and R31).

  15. 15.

    Buridan famously rejected this claim in his later writings, saying not that every proposition signifies its own truth, but that it virtually implies it. His main reason for doing so was his rejection of the notion of the complexly signifiable (complexe significabile), what is signifiable only by a complexum, that is, a proposition. Given the similarity between this doctrine and Burley’s notion of the real proposition, Bradwardine would not share Buridan’s worries, if he did indeed accept Burley’s semantic account. See, e.g. (Klima 2009, Chaps. 910, esp. § 10.2).

  16. 16.

    See (Burley 1955, p. 25, 2000, p. 108): “Quaelibet propositio asserit seipsam esse veram,” and (Roure 1970, p. 272): “Quilibet dicens asserit suum dictum esse verum”.

  17. 17.

    See Lib. I Questiones 7–9 § 10 (Andrews et al. 2004, I p. 181): “Quaelibet propositio significat se esse veram, ergo ista ‘tu eris albus cras’ significat se esse veram. Antecedens patet, quia ad omnem propositionem veram sequitur suum dictum fore verum. Similiter contradictorium affirmativae ut ista ‘tu non eris albus’ infert hanc ‘“te non fore album” est verum’. Utrumque igitur contradictoriorum in illis de futuro significat se esse determinate veram.” This occurs as part of an objection, but in his response Scotus does not question the basic principle.

  18. 18.

    Quaestiones disputatae de mysterio Trinitatis, q1 a1, translated in (Wippel and Wolter 1969, pp. 310–311).

  19. 19.

    (Geulincx 1663, Chap. 1; Land 1891, II p. 25): “Sit enunciatio quaecunque, nempe A. Dico quod A dicat se esse veram. Quia A dicit esse, et dicit esse quod dicit esse, sed esse id, quod A esse dicit, est A esse veram. Cum igitur A prius dicat, dicit etiam posterius, seu A dicet A, id est seipsam, veram esse.” Cf. (Geulincx 1662, II.i.1.4; Land 1891, I p. 234]) and (Nuchelmans 1988, p. 280]). Similar proofs are found in Albert of Saxony and John Buridan. See, e.g., (Read 2002, § 3]).

  20. 20.

    See, e.g., (Yrjönsuuri 1993).

  21. 21.

    See (Read 2008, p. 217).

  22. 22.

    So called from (Curry 1942). Cf. (Geach 1955).

  23. 23.

    See (Roure 1962, p. 262).

  24. 24.

    So called by (Geach 1955): in symbols, from \(p\to (p\to q)\) infer \(p\to q\); nowadays usually referred to as “contraction”.

  25. 25.

    (Del Punta and McCord Adams 1978, p. 74), my translation.

  26. 26.

    We can capture this in a generalisation of (P2): if s signifies that p 1 and signifies that p 2, and p 1 and p 2 (jointly) entail r, then s signifies that r.

References

  • Anderson, A., & Belnap, N. (1975). Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity (Vol. 1). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, R., Etzkorn, G., Gál, G., Green, G., Noone, T., Plevano, R., Traver, R., & Wood, R. (2004). B. Ioannis Duns Scoti: Opera Philosophica. St. Bonaventure: The Franciscan Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnauld, A., & Nicole, P. (1662). La logique ou l’art de penser. Paris: Charles Savreux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradwardine, T. (2010). Insolubilia (trans: S. Read). Leuven: Peeters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, S. (1973). Walter Burley’s middle commentary on Aristotle’s Perihermenias.Franciscan Studies, 33, 42–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buridan, J. (2001). Summulae de Dialectica (trans: G. Klima). New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buridan, J. (2004). Summulae de Practica Sophismatum (Ed. F. Pironet). Turnhout: Brépols.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burley, W. (1955). De Puritate Artis Logicae Tractatus Longior, with a revised edition of the Tractatus Brevior. St. Bonaventure: The Franciscan Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burley, W. (2000). On the purity of the art of logic (trans: P. V. Spade). New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cesalli, L. (2007). Le réalisme propositionnel. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conti, A. (2011). Walter Burley. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. (Fall 2014 edition) http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/burley/.

  • Curry, H. (1942). On the inconsistency of certain formal logics. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 7, 115–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Rijk, L. (1972). Peter of Spain: Tractatus. Assen: Van Gorcum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Del Punta, F., & McCord Adams, M. (1978). Pauli Veneti Logica Magna: Secunda Pars, Tractatus de Veritate et Falsitate Propositionis, et Tractatus de Significato Propositionis. Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2008). Saving truth from paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1997). Thoughts. In M. Beaney (Ed.), A Frege Reader (pp. 325–345). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. (1955). On insolubilia. Analysis, 15, 71–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geulincx, A. (1662). Logica fundamentis suis, a quibus hactenus collapsa fuerat, restituta. Leiden: Henricus Verbiest. (Reprinted in (Land 1891, Vol. I, pp. 165–454)).

    Google Scholar 

  • Geulincx, A. (1663). Methodus inveniendi argumenta. Leiden: Issacus deWael. (Reprinted in (Land 1891, vol. II, pp. 1–111)).

    Google Scholar 

  • Green-Pedersen, N. J. (1980). Walter Burley’s De consequentiis: An edition. Franciscan Studies, 40, 102–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, W. (1863). On presentative and representative knowledge. In W. Hamilton (Ed.), The works of Thomas Reid (Vol. 2, pp. 804–815). Edinburgh: MacLachlan and Stewart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacquette, D. (2007a). Burleigh’s fallacy. Philosophy, 82, 437–448.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacquette, D. (2007b). Deductivism and the informal fallacies. Argumentation, 21, 335–347.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, J. (2007). The nature and structure of content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klima, G. (2009). John Buridan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Land, J. (Ed.). (1891). Arnold Geulincx: Opera Philosophica (3 volumes). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2004). Truth and paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nuchelmans, G. (1988). Geulincx’ containment theory of logic. Medelingen van de Afdeling Letterkunde. Amsterdam: Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, NS51, no. 8, pp. 266–317.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuchelmans, G. (1994). Walter Burleigh on the conclusion that you are an ass. Vivarium, 32, 90–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raine, J. (Ed.). (1843). The correspondence of Dr. Matthew Hutton, Archbishop of York. London: Publications of the Surtees Society 17. J.B. Nichols and Son.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, S. (2002). The liar paradox from John Buridan back to Thomas Bradwardine. Vivarium, 40, 189–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Read, S. (2008). Further thoughts on Tarski’s T-scheme and the Liar. In J. Rahman, T. Tulenheimo, & E. Genot (Eds.), Unity, truth and the liar: The modern relevance of medieval solutions to the liar paradox (pp. 205–225). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ricardus. (n.d.). Abstractiones (Ed. P. King). http://www.hs-augsburg.de/~harsch/Chronologia/Lspost13/RicardusSophista/ricabst.html.

  • Roure, M.-L. (1962). Le traité “Des Propositions Insolubles” de Jean de Celaya. Archives d’Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Age, 29, 235–336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roure, M.-L. (1970). La problématique des propositions insolubles au XIIIe siècle et au début du XIVe, suivie de l’édition des traités de W. Shyreswood, W. Burleigh et Th. Bradwardine. Archives d’Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Age, 37, 205–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1903). The principles of mathematics. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spade, P. (1981). ‘Insolubilia’ and Bradwardine’s theory of signification. Medioevo, 7, 115–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wippel, J., & Wolter, A. (Eds.). (1969). Medieval philosophy. NewYork: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yrjönsuuri, M. (1993). Expositio as a method of solving sophisms. In S. Read (Ed.), Sophisms in medieval logic and grammar (pp. 202–216). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephen Read .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Read, S. (2015). Truth, Signification and Paradox. In: Achourioti, T., Galinon, H., Martínez Fernández, J., Fujimoto, K. (eds) Unifying the Philosophy of Truth. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 36. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9673-6_20

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics