Skip to main content

Comparability of Infinities and Infinite Multitude in Galileo and Leibniz

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
G.W. Leibniz, Interrelations between Mathematics and Philosophy

Part of the book series: Archimedes ((ARIM,volume 41))

  • 1133 Accesses

Abstract

This paper examines the concepts of infinite multitude and comparability of size in Galileo’s discussion of the paradox of the natural numbers in Two New Sciences, and related points in Leibniz’s philosophy. Galileo’s celebrated denial that ‘greater’, ‘less’, and ‘equal’ apply in the infinite threatens two important mathematical principles: Euclid’s Axiom and the Bijection Principle of Cardinal Equality. I consider two potential strategies open to Galileo for preserving the principles, of which the more promising is due to Leibniz. I find, contrary to the customary view, that Galileo’s denial is limited to comparisons among infinite magnitudes and allows judgments of cardinal equality among infinite multitudes, based on one-one correspondences. The paper’s analysis also reveals how intimately related Leibniz’s definition of ‘infinite’ is to Galileo’s discussion, and illuminates key contrasts between their accounts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Knobloch (1999; 2011).

  2. 2.

    Primary texts are abbreviated as follows. For Galileo: EN = Opere, Edizione Nazionale, ed. Antonio Favaro (Florence 1898). For Leibniz: A = Berlin Academy Edition, Sämtliche Schriften un Briefe. Philosophische Schriften. Series VI. Vols. 1–4. (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1923−99); GP = Gerhardt, Die Philosophischen Schriften, Vols. 1–7. Ed. C.I. Gerhardt (Berlin: Weidmannsche, Buchhandlung 18751890); GM = Mathematische Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Vols. 1–7. Ed. C.I. Gerhardt (Berlin: A. Asher; Halle: H.W. Schmidt 18491863). References to EN, GP and GM are to volume and page numbers; those to A are to series, volume and page. Translations of Galileo generally follow those of Stillman Drake (abbreviated ‘D’), Galileo Galilei: Two New Sciences, Including Centers of Gravity and force of Percussion, 2nd Ed, (Toronto: Wall and Emerson, Inc. 1974), and those of Leibniz generally follow Richard Arthur (abbreviated ‘Ar’), G.W. Leibniz: The Labyrinth of the Continuum: Writings on the Continuum Problem, 1672–1686 (New Haven: Yale University Press 2001). I have sometimes modified translations without comment.

  3. 3.

    A quick note on terminology. In what follows I sometimes use the terms ‘class’, ‘subclass’, etc., for convenience, but without meaning to imply that the many elements of a class thereby form a set or totality or other ‘single object.’ (Mostly here it will cause no harm to read ‘class’ and ‘set’ as equivalent, but sometimes it will lead astray, so beware.) Occurrences of ‘class’, etc., can, with appropriate shifts in syntax, always be replaced by suitable plural expressions—e.g., ‘the natural numbers’ instead of ‘the class of natural numbers’—or by terms such as ‘multitude’ or ‘plurality’ that cancel the implication of one thing formed from many. In contexts in which greater precision is required to convey the intended meaning, and avoid unwanted implications, I shall use unambiguous terms.

  4. 4.

    Cantor writes, “There is no contradiction when, as often happens with infinite aggregates, two aggregates of which one is a part of the other have the same cardinal number” (Cantor 1915, p. 75; noted in Parker (2009)) .

  5. 5.

    Russell (1913, p. 198).

  6. 6.

    For a very illuminating discussion of the history of the idea of measuring the size of the natural number collections, as it has evolved up to Cantor, plus some contemporary alternatives to Cantor, see Mancosu (2009).

  7. 7.

    In the usual formula: S is infinite if and only if there is a one-one map Φ from S into S with some element of S not in the range of Φ. Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?, Sect. 64; cf. Sect 66.

  8. 8.

    Crew and de Salvio’s 1914 translation renders tutti i numeri as “the totality of all numbers” (cf. p. 31). In the same lines it also inserts ‘number’ in “the number of squares is infinite” and “the number of roots is infinite”, where the corresponding term does not occur in the original. Drake’s translation steers clear of those interpolations.

  9. 9.

    Knobloch (1999), p. 94.

  10. 10.

    My discussion is indebted to Parker (2009), who, defensibly, calls our two principles ‘Euclid’s Principle’ and ‘Hume’s Principle’ . If Galileo had not rejected the one-one maps standard in the infinite case, we should call it ‘Galileo’s Principle’. For reasons to think Archimedes made use of this principle in application to infinite classes, see Netz et al. (20012002) .

  11. 11.

    Notably those involved in discussion of a similar principle of equality sometimes called ‘Hume’s Principle’: the number of Fs equals the number of Gs iff there is a one-one correspondence between the Fs and the Gs. The principle is so-called for Frege’s reference, in Sect. 73 of the Foundations of Mathematics, to Hume’s remark, in Treatise I.iii.1, “When two numbers are so combin’d as that one has always an unite answering to every unite of the other, we pronounce them equal.” Yet both of those authors have their sights on slightly more restricted conditions than the ones Galileo considers. Frege takes one-one correspondence between classes to imply the existence of a number that measures them; Hume \t "See Principle" is expressly considering a standard of equality for numbers, where the numbers themselves are conceived as made up of units. It is in this vein that one-one correspondence is sometimes said to be a criterion of ‘equinumerosity’: equality of number.

  12. 12.

    Or he appears to be doing so. Below I shall suggest his account of comparisons of infinite number classes turns out to involve an infinite number after all; that is, if, per impossibile, there were such a comparison, it would have to involve an infinite number.

  13. 13.

    See footnote 3 above.

  14. 14.

    Bolzano, for example, explicitly defended the primacy of Euclid’s Axiom against the Bijection Principle, writing that even two sets that stand in a one-one correspondence “can still stand in a relation of inequality in the sense that the one is found to be a whole, and the other a part of that whole” (Bolzano 1950, p. 98). For discussion of Bolzano, see Parker (2009) and Mancosu (2009). Even Russell acknowledged that “the possibility that the whole and part may have the same number of terms is, it must be confessed, shocking to common sense” (1903, p. 358).

  15. 15.

    On “wielding the big stick”, see Michael Dummett (1994) .

  16. 16.

    It should be noted that Galileo’s analysis is mistaken—at most one of the two circles rolls along the tangent, the other merely revolves continuously along it with the illusion of rolling—but our interest concerns the elements of his analysis, not the quality of his solution. For detailed discussion see Drabkin (1950) , Costabel (1964) , and Knobloch (1999, 2011). See also Mancosu (1996, pp. 121–122).

  17. 17.

    Knobloch (1999, p. 92).

  18. 18.

    This runs parallel to the classical contemporary point-set analysis, which allows unions of infinitely many zero-dimensional points (or singletons) to have any positive measure, though with the proviso, on the contemporary account, that the cardinality of the union be uncountable; countably infinite unions of points would still have measure zero. See Skyrms (1983) .

  19. 19.

    Perhaps an expansion by mere rearrangement of non quanti atoms would seem to violate conservation principles, whereas the interposition of non quanti voids would not, if void is not a conserved quantity, so to speak.

  20. 20.

    For provocative discussion of the bisection principle and its possible denial, see Benardete (1964, pp. 240 ff).

  21. 21.

    Knobloch (1999, p. 93; 2011).

  22. 22.

    Another possibility is that Galileo’s denial that ‘greater’, ‘less’ and ‘equal’ apply in the infinite is carefully consistent with his judgments that there as just as many Xs as Ys in some cases of infinite multitudes: perhaps the Xs and the Ys can be just as many without falling under the term ‘equal’. If so, however, it would seem to be only a matter of a word, as no richer notion of cardinal equality seems available for which ‘just as many’ is not sufficient. A more substantial possibility here would be that for Galileo, ‘greater’, ‘less’ and ‘equal’ are essentially metrical notions, and their cardinal counterparts ‘more’, ‘fewer’ and ‘equally many’ cannot be applied on the basis of one-one maps without corresponding geometrical judgments in place as well. I am more sympathetic to this idea but cannot pursue it here; a few related points are discussed below.

  23. 23.

    I am indebted here to Katherine Dunlop.

  24. 24.

    Knobloch (1999, p. 92). See also Knobloch (2011).

  25. 25.

    See Nicholas ([1440] 1985), De Docta Ignorantia, Book 1, Chaps. 11–23; see especially Chap. 14 for use of the distinction between quanta and non quanta.

  26. 26.

    This so-called Diagonal Paradox was well-known by the seventeenth century; see Leibniz’s use of it at A VI, 3, 199. As noted by Lison (2006/2007, p. 199fn3) , the example goes back at least to Ockham. Note also that similar examples can be constructed even with multitudes containing only quanti parts, provided their total measure remains finitely bounded. Considering a line segment as composed of a sequence of geometrically decreasing non-overlapping subsegments, one can easily construct a one-one correspondence between the subsegments of the side of a square and the subsegments of the diagonal, even though the side can be shown by rotation to be equal to a part of the diagonal.

  27. 27.

    For related discussion, see Levey (1998)and Arthur’s introduction to Leibniz(2001).

  28. 28.

    Leibniz has a few different lines of argument to offer against infinite number, including, notably for us, a deployment of Galileo’s paradox that expressly says infinite numbers are “impossible” because “it is impossible that this axiom”—Euclid’s Axiom—“fails” (A III, 1, 11). (This passage comes from some remarks by Leibniz on Galileo’s paradox, written in 1673.) Here an infinite number is presumably understood as a whole constituted of infinitely many units or the combination of all natural numbers, themselves taken as wholes composed of units. For some related discussion, see Levey (1998).

  29. 29.

    At Grua 558 Leibniz writes: “God is not the soul of the world can be demonstrated; for the world is either finite or infinite. If the world is finite, certainly God, who is infinite, cannot be said to be the soul of the World. If the world is supposed to be infinite, it is not one Being or one body per se (just as it has elsewhere been demonstrated that infinite in number and in magnitude is neither one nor a whole, but infinite in perfection is one and a whole). Thus no soul of this sort can be understood. An infinite world, of course, is no more one [Being] and a whole than an infinite number, which Galileo has demonstrated to be neither one nor a whole.”(Leibniz 1948, p. 558).

  30. 30.

    For an overview of this dispute in the interpretation of Leibniz, see Levey (2011).

  31. 31.

    See Leibniz (2007), p. 409.

  32. 32.

    Drake suggests that Galileo neither fully accepted nor fully rejected Aristotle’s principle (1974, 42fn26).

  33. 33.

    See Levey (1998, 1999, 2003). For defense of the view that Leibniz’s strictures against infinite wholes only preclude wholes of infinite magnitude, and thus can allow wholes of finite magnitude that include infinitely elements, see Brown (2005).

  34. 34.

    See Ishiguro (1990) , Knobloch (1994, 2002), Bassler (1998), Arthur (2008), (2009) and (2013) and Levey (2008). In the present paper it’s worth noting that the same crossed-out passage that contains the denial of cardinal equality between the evens and odds, Leibniz begins: “There is a syncategorematic infinite or passive power having parts, namely, the possibility of further progress by dividing, multiplying, subtracting, or adding. And there is a hypercategorematic infinite, or potestative infinite, an active power having, as it were, parts eminently but not formally or actually. This infinite is God himself. But there is not a categorematic infinite or one actually having infinite parts formally” (GP II, 314–315). Translated by Look and Rutherford in Leibniz (2007, p. 53).

  35. 35.

    William Heytesbury may have been the first to defend a syncategorematic analysis of ‘infinite’; see sophisma xviii of his Sophismata, in Pironet (1994) .

  36. 36.

    Quoted in Grosholz and Yakira (1998, p. 99 ).

  37. 37.

    See my ‘Leibniz’s Analysis of Galileo’s Paradox,’ ms.

References

  • Arthur, Richard. 2008. Leery bedfellows: Leibniz and Newton on the status of infinitesimals. In Infinitesimals differences: Controversies between Leibniz and his contemporaries, ed. U. Goldenbaum and D. Jesseph, 7–30. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, Richard. 2009. Actuals infinitesimals in Leibniz’s early thought. In The philosophy of the young Leibniz (Studia LeibnitianaSonderheft 35), ed. M. Kulstad, M. Laerk, and D. Snyder, 11–28. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag),

    Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, Richard. 2013. Leibniz’s syncategorematic infinitesimals. Archive for History of Exact Sciences 67:553–593.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bassler, O. Bradley. 1998. Leibniz on the indefinite as infinite. The Review of Metaphysics 15: 849–874.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benardete, José. 1964. IInfinity: An essay in metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolzano, Bernard. 1851/1950. Paradoxes of the infinite (translated by F. Prihonsky). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Gregory. 2005. Leibniz’s mathematical argument against a Soul of the World. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 13:449’488.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantor, Georg. 1915. Contributions to the founding of the theory of transfinite numbers (Translated and edited by Philip Jourdain). New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costabel, Pierre. 1964. La roue d’Aristote et les critiques françaises à l’argument de Galilée. Revue d’Histoire des Sciences 17:385–396.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drabkin, I. E. 1950. Aristotle’s wheel: Notes on the history of a paradox. Osiris 9:126–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, Michael. 1994. What is mathematics about? In Mathematics and mind, ed. Alexander George, 11–26. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei, Galileo. 1898. Opere, Vols. 1–8. ed. Antonio Favaro. Florence: Edizione Nazionale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei, Galileo. 1974. Two new sciences, including centers of gravity and force of percussion, 2nd edn. (Translated and edited with commentary by Stillman Drake). Toronto: Wall and Emerson, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosholz, Emily, and Elhanan Yakira. 1998. Leibniz’s science of the rational. Studia leibnitiana— Sonderhefte 26. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ishiguro, Hidé. 1990. Leibniz’s philosophy of logic and language, 2nd edn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobloch, Eberhard. 1994. The infinite in Leibniz’s mathematics: The historiographical method of comprehension in context. In Trends in the Historiography of Science, ed. Kostas Gavroglu et al., 265–278. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobloch, Eberhard. 1999. Galileo and Leibniz: Different approaches to infinity. Archive for History of Exact Sciences 54:87–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobloch, Eberhard. 2002. Leibniz’s rigorous foundation of infinitesimal geometry by means of riemannian sums. Synthese 133 (1–2): 59–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobloch, Eberhard. 2011. Galileo and German thinkers: Leibniz. In Galileo e la scuola galileiana nelle Università del Seicento, ed. L. Pepe, 127–139. Bologna: Cooperativa Libraria Universitaria Bologna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G.W. 1849–1863. Mathematische Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Vols. 1–7 (Ed. C.I. Gerhardt). Berlin: A. Asher; Halle: H.W. Schmidt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G.W. 1875–1890. Die Philosophischen Schriften. Vols. 1–7 (Ed. C.I. Gerhardt). Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G.W. 1923–1999. Samtliche Schriften un Briefe. Philosophische Schriften. Series VI. Vols. 1–4. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G.W. 1948. Texts inédits d’apres les manuscits de la bibliothéque provinciale de Hanover. Vols. 1–2. Edited by Gaston Grua. Paris: P.U.F.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G.W. 2001. Labyrinth of the continuum: writings on the continuum problem, 1672–1686. Translated and edited with commentary by Richard T. W. Arthur. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G.W. 2007. The Leibniz-Des Bosses correspondence. Translated and edited with commentary by Brandon Look and Donald Rutherford. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levey, Samuel. 1998. Leibniz on mathematics and the actually infinite division of matter. The Philosophical Review 107 (1): 49–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levey, Samuel. 1999. Leibniz’s constructivism and infinitely folded matter. In New essays on the rationalists, ed. Rocco J. Gennaro and Charles Huenemann, 134–162. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levey, Samuel. 2003. The interval of motion in Leibniz’s Pacidius Philalethi. Noûs 37:317–416.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levey, Samuel. 2008. Archimedes, infinitesimals and the law of continuity: On leibniz’s fictionalism. In Infinitesimals differences: Controversies between Leibniz and his contemporaries, ed. U. Goldenbaum and D. Jesseph, 107–134. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levey, Samuel. 2011. On two theories of substance in Leibniz: Critical notice of Daniel Garber, Leibniz: Body, Substance, Monad. The Philosophical Review 120:285–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lison, Elad. 2006/2007. The philosophical assumptions underlying Leibniz’s use of the diagonal paradox in 1672. Studia Leibnitiana 38/39:197–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, Paulo. 1996. Philosophy of mathematics and mathematical practice in the seventeenth century. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, Paulo. 2009. Measuring the size of infinite collections of natural numbers: Was cantor’s theory of infinite numbers inevitable? Review of Symbolic Logic 2:612–646.

    Google Scholar 

  • Netz, R., K. Saito, and N. Techenetska. 2001–2002. A new reading of method proposition 14 from the Archimedes Palimpsest (Parts 1 and 2). Sciamus 2–3:9–29 and 109–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicholas of Cusa. 1440/1985. On learned ignorance. In Nicholas of Cusa on Learned Ignorance: A Translation and Appraisal of De Docta Ignorantia, ed. Jasper Hopkins, 2nd ed. Minneapolis: Arthur J. Banning Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, Matthew W. 2009. Philosophical method and galileo’s Paradox of infinity. In New perspectives on mathematical practices, ed. Bart Van Kerkhove, 76–113. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pironet, Fabienne, ed. 1994. Guillaume Heytesbury, Sophismata asinina. Une introduction aux disputes médiévales. Présentation, édition critique et analyse. , ed. Bart Van Kerkhove, 76– 113. Collection Sic et Non; Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1903. The principles of mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1914. Our knowledge of the external world. Chicago: Open Court Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, Brian. 1983. Zeno’s Paradox of Measure. In Physics, philosophy and psychoanalysis, ed. R. S. Cohen and L. Lauden, 223–254. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

My thanks to Katherine Dunlop , Jeffrey McDonough, O. Bradley Bassler , Richard Arthur , Philip Beeley and Norma Goethe for helpful comments, and to audiences at the University of Oxford and Texas A&M University who heard preliminary versions of this material. My thanks also to Michael Detlefsen for the invitation that eventually led to this work, to Eberhard Knobloch whose skepticism about my claims about Galileo in an earlier paper made me to reconsider the issues more carefully, and especially to Norma Goethe, again, who encouraged me to write the present paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Samuel Levey .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Levey, S. (2015). Comparability of Infinities and Infinite Multitude in Galileo and Leibniz. In: Goethe, N., Beeley, P., Rabouin, D. (eds) G.W. Leibniz, Interrelations between Mathematics and Philosophy. Archimedes, vol 41. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9664-4_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics