Skip to main content

Knowing Thyself in a Contemporary Context: A Fresh Look at Heideggerian Authenticity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Horizons of Authenticity in Phenomenology, Existentialism, and Moral Psychology

Part of the book series: Contributions To Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 74))

  • 1458 Accesses

Abstract

The authors provide an analysis of Heidegger’s critique of the narrowness of the modern worldview, and the modern self in particular, in an attempt to understand what the meaning of human existence is for Heidegger. Heidegger criticizes the prevalent view of the self as divorced from the world and from others, showing that the nature of human being involves immersion in the world as a fundamentally social entity. While commentators on Heidegger often juxtapose the early Heidegger with the later Heidegger, the authors show a cord of resonance with the early Heideggerian concept of authenticity [Eigentlichkeit] and the later Heideggerian notion of dwelling [wohnen], thereby providing a coherent interpretation of authenticity in Heidegger’s thought by focusing on the structural similarities between the two. The authors argue in the end that Heidegger’s notion of dwelling among things of significance provides a contemporary version of what it means to “know thyself” today.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Henry George Liddell and Robert Scott note that ὑποκείμενον comes from ὑπόκειμαι, which means “to lie under or beneath” (2003, 843).

  2. 2.

    Those interested in the relation between Descartes and medieval philosophy should consult Roger Ariew’s Descartes among the Scholastics (2011).

  3. 3.

    For a more thorough discussion of this topic, see Guignon 1983, Chap. 1.

  4. 4.

    As Heidegger states, “Now the more unequivocally one maintains that knowing is proximally and really ‘inside’ […], the less one presupposes when one believes that one is making headway in the question of the essence of knowledge and in the clarification of the relationship between subject and Object. For only then can the problem arise of how this knowing subject comes out of its inner ‘sphere’ into one which is ‘other and external’, of how knowing can have any object at all, and of how one must think of the object itself so that eventually the subject knows it without needing to venture a leap into another sphere” (BT, 87/SZ, 60).

  5. 5.

    Macquarrie and Robinson capitalize their translation of “Sein” and its derivatives (e.g. “in-der-Welt-sein”); we render all such instances with the lower-case.

  6. 6.

    We should point out that the word “Others” has a technical meaning for Heidegger. “Others” does not mean everyone but myself; rather, “they are…those from whom, for the most part, one does not distinguish oneself—those among whom one is too” (BT, 154/SZ, 118). In other words, there is no fundamental separation between Others and myself for Heidegger.

  7. 7.

    In section 64 of Being and Time, Heidegger makes continual reference to the “I” and appears to be carrying out an analysis of the first-person (BT, 364-70/SZ, 316–323). We must not take too much from this for the following reasons. For one, most of the discussion involves an interpretation of Kant, and Heidegger is making use of Kant’s terminology. Indeed, this is indicated by his repeated use of scare quotes when referencing the “I.” Some of Heidegger’s closing remarks also make it clear that the question of the “I” will not be central to his inquiry, but is in fact posterior and dependent upon a more primordial understanding of the self: “As something that keeps silent, authentic being-one’s-Self is just the sort of thing that does not keep on saying ‘I’; but in its reticence it ‘is’ that thrown entity as which it can authentically be. The Self which the reticence of resolute existence unveils is the primordial phenomenal basis for the question as to the being of the ‘I’. […] In the prevalent way of saying ‘I’, it is constantly suggested that what we have in advance is a Self-Thing, persistently present-at-hand; the ontological question of the being of the Self must turn away from any such suggestion” (BT, 369-70/SZ, 322–323). For these reasons, there is scarcely another mention of the “I” in the rest of Being and Time.

  8. 8.

    “Dasein is falling into the ‘they’ (in being-already-amidst the world of its concern), and it is summoned out of this falling by the appeal” (BT, 322/SZ, 277, translation modified).

  9. 9.

    “Dasein’s absorption in the ‘they’ and its absorption in the ‘world’ of its concern, make manifest something like a fleeing of Dasein in the face of itself – of itself as an authentic potentiality-for-being-its-Self” (BT, 229/SZ, 184).

  10. 10.

    The notion of a paradigm is invoked by Thomas Kuhn (1970). The notion of a cultural paradigm comes from Clifford Geertz (1973).

References

  • Ariew, Roger. 2011. Descartes among the scholastics. Leiden: Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1985. The Politics. Trans. Carnes Lord. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carman, Taylor. 2005. Authenticity. In A companion to Heidegger, ed. Hubert L. Dreyfus and Mark A. Wrathall, 285–296. Malden: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, Steven. 2005. Subjectivity: Locating the first-person in Being and Time. In Heidegger’s being and time: Critical essays, ed. Richard Polt, 117–139. Lanham: Roman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert L. 1991. Being-in-the-world: A commentary on Heidegger’s being and time, division I. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert L. 1993. Heidegger on the connection between nihilism, art, technology, and politics. In The Cambridge companion to Heidegger, ed. Charles Guignon, 345–372. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geertz, Clifford. 1973. The interpretation of cultures. New York: Harper Colophon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guignon, Charles. 1983. Heidegger and the problem of knowledge. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guignon, Charles. 2004. On being authentic. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guignon, Charles. 2008. Authenticity. Philosophy Compass 3: 277–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guignon, Charles. 2011. Heidegger’s concept of freedom, 1927–1930. In Interpreting Heidegger: Critical essays, ed. Daniel O. Dahlstrom, 79–105. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1953. Sein und Zeit (SZ). Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and Time (BT). Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1971. The thing. In Poetry, Language, Thought (PLT), 161–184. Trans. Albert Hofstadter. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1973. Metaphysics as history of being. In The End of Philosophy (EP), 1–54. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1977. The age of the world picture. In The Question Concerning Technology and Other Writings (QCT), 115–154. Trans. William Lovitt. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1982. Nietzsche volume IV: Nihilism (N IV). In Nietzsche: Volumes III and IV, 289–301, ed. David Farrell Krell, Trans. Frank A. Capuzzi. San Francisco: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1988. Basic Problems of Phenomenology (BP), rev. ed. Trans. Albert Hofstadter. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1992. History of the Concept of Time: Prolegomena (HCT). Trans. Theodore Kisiel. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1993a. Building dwelling thinking. In Basic writings (BW), rev. and exp. edition, ed. David Farrell Krell, 343–363. San Francisco: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1993b. Origin of the work of art. In Basic writings, rev. and exp. edition, ed. David Farrell Krell, 139–212. San Francisco: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1994. Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (GA 20), 3rd ed, ed. Petra Jaeger. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1995a. Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (GA 24), ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1995b. Feldweg-Gespräche (GA 77), ed. Ingrid Schüßler. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1997. Nietzsche (GA 6.2), ed. Brigitte Schillbach. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2000. Vorträge und Aufsätze, (GA 7), ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2003a. Holzwege, (GA 5), 2nd ed, ed. Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2003b. Zähringen Seminar. In Four Seminars (FS), 64–84. Trans. Andrew Mitchell and François Raffoul. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2005. Seminare, (GA 15), ed. Curd Ochwadt. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2010. Evening conversation: In a prisoner of war camp in Russia, between a younger and an older man. In Country Path Conversations (CPC), 132–160. Trans. Bret W. Davis. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas. 1970. The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liddell, Henry George, and Robert Scott. 2003. An intermediate Greek-English lexicon. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1967. The Will to Power, ed. Walter Kaufmann. Trans. Walter Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the self: The making of the modern identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 2007. A secular age. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Julian. 2006. The fourfold. In The Cambridge companion to Heidegger, ed. Charles Guignon, 373–392. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Michael. 1981. Eclipse of the self: The development of Heidegger’s concept of authenticity. Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steven Burgess .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Burgess, S., Rentmeester, C. (2015). Knowing Thyself in a Contemporary Context: A Fresh Look at Heideggerian Authenticity. In: Pedersen, H., Altman, M. (eds) Horizons of Authenticity in Phenomenology, Existentialism, and Moral Psychology. Contributions To Phenomenology, vol 74. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9442-8_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics