Skip to main content

The Concept of Best Interests in Clinical Practice

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Children’s Well-Being: Indicators and Research ((CHIR,volume 9))

Abstract

The Best Interests Standard is a difficult and controversial concept, and its implementation in clinical practice faces substantial concerns from conceptual and linguistic points of view.

By analyzing the underlying premises I conclude in a first step that the often criticized inconsistencies is not as much a problem of the concept of best interests itself but rather an inevitable consequence of coherent tensions between different values and perspectives in clinical practice. Nevertheless by pretending normative statements without the argumentative groundwork the term of “best interests” is prone to become empty or rhetorical. For using “best interests” as a meaningful concept and to respect and to consider the sometimes conflicting needs, values and perspectives in clinical practice I propose a constitutional matrix with three different discourses and four stakeholders. Arguing with the concept of “best interests” therefore implies to understand underlying ideologies (1), to delineate a particular area of optimum care and choice (2), and to learn about established or needed thresholds (3). Furthermore these three discourses are informed, each in a particular manner, by the views of expert (1), parents (2), the child (3) and the knowledge of a prospective future person (4). If only one of these considerations is missing we either should conceive the concept of “best interests” as a mandate to complete these considerations or refrain from using it in our argumentation. As a consequence the best interests is not perceived as a particular principle or philosophical argument but as a complex claim to assess and to implement multifaceted needs, aims, conditions and arguments concerning a child.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Feinberg’s approach fails to show why the open future argument is applicable on children (e.g. desires and whishes in childhood should be sacrificed for the opportunities of an adult person in her 30s) but not on adults (e.g. desires and whishes of a person in her 20s should be sacrificed for the opportunities of an adult person in her 60s).

References

  • Ainsworth, F., & Hansen, P. (2011). The experience of parents of children in care: The human rights issue. Child & Youth Services, 32(1), 9–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alderson, P. (1992). In the genes or in the stars? Children’s competence to consent. Journal of Medical Ethics, 18(3), 119–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • American Academy of Pediatrics. (2003). Family pediatrics: Report of the task force on the family. Pediatrics, 111(6), 1541–1571.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, K., Ryan, C. A., Hawkes, C. P., Janvier, A., & Dempsey, E. M. (2011). Life and death decisions for incompetent patients: determining best interests – The Irish perspective. Acta Paediatrica, 100(4), 519–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bricher, G. (2000). Children in the hospital: Issues of power and vulnerability. Pediatric Nursing, 26(3), 277–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A. E., & Brock, D. W. (1989). Deciding for others: The ethics of surrogate decision making. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, W. (2002). Family-focused pediatrics: A primary care family systems approach to psychosocial problems. Current Problems in Pediatric and Adolescent Health Care, 32(8), 260–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Committee on Bioethics. (2007). Professionalism in pediatrics: Statement of principles. Pediatrics, 120(4), 895–897.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Committee on Hospital Care and Institute for Patient- and Family-Centered Care. (2012). Patient- and family-centered care and the pediatrician’s role. Pediatrics, 129(2), 394–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Committee on the Rights of Children. (1989). Convention on the rights of the child. United Nations Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diekema, D. (2004). Parental refusals of medical treatment: The harm principle as threshold for state intervention. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 25(4), 243–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diekema, D. S. (2011). Revisiting the best interest standard: Uses and misuses. The Journal of Clinical Ethics, 22(2), 128–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downie, R. S., & Randall, F. (1997). Parenting and the best interests of minors. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 22(3), 219–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1980). The child’s right to an open future. In W. Aiken & H. Lafollette (Eds.), Whose child? Children’s rights, parental authority, and state power (pp. 76–97). Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, M., & Solnit, A. J. (1964). Reactions to the threatened loss of a child: a vulnerable child syndrome. Pediatric management of the dying child. Pediatrics, 34, 58–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallström, I., & Elander, G. (2005). Decision making in paediatric care: An overview with reference to nursing care. Nursing Ethics, 12(3), 223–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinds, P. S., Oakes, L. L., Hicks, J., Powell, B., Srivastava, D. K., Spunt, S. L., Harper, J., Baker, J. N., West, N. K., & Furman, W. L. (2009). “Trying to be a good parent” as defined by interviews with parents who made phase I, terminal care, and resuscitation decisions for their children. Journal of Clinical Oncology, 27(35), 5979–5985.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holm, S., & Edgar, A. (2008). Best interest: A philosophical critique. Health Care Analysis, 16(3), 197–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, B., Kleinemeier, E., Lux, A., Hiort, O., Grüters, A., & Thyen, U. (2012). Satisfaction with genital surgery and sexual life of adults with XY disorders of sex development: Results from the German clinical evaluation study. The Journal of Clinical Endocrinology and Metabolism, 97(2), 577–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kopelman, L. M. (1997). The best-interests standard as threshold, ideal, and standard of reasonableness. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 22(3), 271–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lansdown, G. (2005). The evolving capacities of the child. Florence: UNICEF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partridge, B. C. (2010). Adolescent psychological development, parenting styles, and pediatric decision making. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 35(5), 518–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salter, E. K. (2012). Deciding for a child: A comprehensive analysis of the best interest standard. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 33(3), 179–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Streuli, J. C. (2011). Ethical Decision Making in Pediatrics – An empirical study on the relationship between “Kindeswohl” and “Best interests” and a proposal to their implementation [in German]. Unpublished, School of Social Work, University of Applied Sciences and Arts Northwestern Switzerland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Streuli, J. C., Michel, M., & Vayena, E. (2011). Children’s rights in pediatrics. European Journal of Pediatrics, 170(1), 9–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Streuli, J. C., Köhler, B., Werner-Rosen, K., & Mitchell, C. (2012). DSD and professionalism from a multilateral view: Supplementing the consensus statement on the basis of a qualitative survey. Advances in Urology, 2012, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Streuli, J. C., Vayena, E., Cavicchia-Balmer, Y., & Huber, J. (2013). Shaping parents: impact of contrasting professional counseling on parents’ decision making for children with disorders of sex development. Journal of Sexual Medicine, 10(8), 1953–1960.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Streuli, J. C., Staubli, G., Pfändler-Poletti, M., Baumann-Hölzle, R., & Ersch, J. (2014). Five-year experience of clinical ethics consultations in a pediatric teaching hospital. European Journal of Pediatrics, 173(5), 629–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winnicott, D. W. (1965). The maturational process and the facilitative environment. New York: International University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jürg C. Streuli .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Streuli, J.C. (2015). The Concept of Best Interests in Clinical Practice. In: Bagattini, A., Macleod, C. (eds) The Nature of Children's Well-Being. Children’s Well-Being: Indicators and Research, vol 9. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9252-3_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics