Skip to main content

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 6))

Abstract

From Platonic and Galenic roots, the first well developed ventricular theory of brain function is due to Bishop Nemesius, fourth century C.E. Although more interested in the Christian concept of soul, St. Augustine, too addressed the question of the location of the soul, a problem that has endured in various guises to the present day. Other notable contributions to ventricular psychology are the ninth century C.E. Arabic writer, Qusta ibn Lūqā, and an early European medical text written by the twelfth century C.E. author, Nicolai the Physician. By the time of Albertus Magnus, so-called medieval cell doctrine was a well-developed model of brain function. By the sixteenth century, Vesalius no longer understands the ventricles to be imaginary cavities designed to provide a physical basis for faculty psychology but as fluid-filled spaces in the brain whose function is yet to be determined.

Author was deceased at the time of publication.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Galen (trans. Brock AJ1916).

  2. 2.

    Galen, De usu partium corporis humani, 1, 491

  3. 3.

    Galen, De usu partium corporis humani, 1, 491

  4. 4.

    Galen on respiration translators. Furley and Wilkie 1984, p. 121.

  5. 5.

    Galen is, in fact, somewhat undecided about how the pneuma psychikon makes its effects felt. In De locis affectis, book 1, chapter 7 (Siegel 1968, pp. 31–32), for example, he eschews the hydrodynamic model, and makes a comparison with the sudden strike of a ray of sunlight. This analogy resonates down the millennia and may be found in Islamic and Medieval texts and makes an appearance as late as the seventeenth century in Willis’s Cerebri anatome (Willis 1681, p. 127).

  6. 6.

    Indeed, a slightly earlier but less well-known version of tripartite ventricular psychology was published by Posidonius of Byzantium in the middle of the fourth century.

  7. 7.

    Nemesius, 8; in Sharples and van der Eijk, 2008, p. 122.

  8. 8.

    Darwin 1801, vol. 1, p. 28: ‘… our ideas are animal motions of the organs of sense.’ See, also, Smith 2005.

  9. 9.

    Nemesius, 2; in Sharples and van der Eijk 2008, p. 55.

  10. 10.

    See Bardy 1953.

  11. 11.

    An account of the debt Augustine owes to Vindicianus’ lost medical treatises is given by Agäesse and Sogignac in St Augustine’s Oeuvres, vol. 48, pp. 710–714.

  12. 12.

    Augustine, De genesi ad litteram,7, 13, 20; in Agäesse and Solignac, 1972.

  13. 13.

    Bacon 1620, p. 46, §199.

  14. 14.

    Augustine, ibid., 7, 13, 20; in Agäesse and Solignac, 1972.

  15. 15.

    Augustine, ibid., 7, 19, 25; in Agäesse and Solignac, 1972.

  16. 16.

    Augustine, ibid., 7,18, 24; in Agäesse and Solignac, 1972.

  17. 17.

    Letter to Jerome (transl, O’Daley 1987), chapter 4: ‘[the soul] is spread throughout the entire body which it animates, not through any local extension, but as a kind of vital tension.’ This idea is common in Stoic philosophy.

  18. 18.

    Augustine, De quantitate animae, XIV, 24.

  19. 19.

    Ibid., 32, §68.

  20. 20.

    The Latin translation of Qusta ibn Lūqā’s treatise was one of the set books in Natural Philosophy in Paris in 1234. A more comprehensive account of ibn Lūqā’s theory may be found in Lokhorst and Kaitaro, 2001.

  21. 21.

    Anatomia Magistri Nicolai Physici.

  22. 22.

    Manzoni 1998

  23. 23.

    Clarke and Dewhurst 1972

  24. 24.

    Bacon: Opus Majus: part V, chapter 2 (Bacon and Bridges 1897): ‘in the anterior part of the first cell is the sensus communis. This takes cognisance of, and distinguishes, the impression brought by each special sense. But it is unable to retain these impressions, being loose and slippery. In the back part of the same cell there is therefore the organ of imagination, which, being neither too moist or too dry, can retain and store up the material received by the sensus communis. Avicenna [he writes] cites, as an example, a seal, the image of which water readily receives but does not retain owing to its superabundant moisture; wax, however, retains the image very well owing to its tempered moistness with dryness. Wherefore, he says, it is one thing to receive, another to retain, as is clear from these examples.…

  25. 25.

    Albertus Magnus: Questions. IV, 9. (in Resnick and Kiitchell 2008, p. 163)

  26. 26.

    Is shape a material concept? It cannot be atomised! The idea that the sensory nerves carry images of the world outside to the brain is, in fact, very ancient and can be found in, for example, Hunayn’s Art of Medicine (c.850 AD) where he combines it with another Galenic idea: that sensory nerves are ‘soft’ whilst motor nerves are ‘hard’. Whereas the sensory nerves are flexible and thus can accommodate the imprints of sensory stimuli, the ‘hardness’ of the motor nerve allows a percussive force to be delivered via the contained animal spirit to the muscles (for further information see Smith et al. 2012).

  27. 27.

    See Marr 1976.

  28. 28.

    In 1484 the Florentine poet Luigi Pulci was denied Christian burial for declaring that the soul was ‘no more than a pine nut in hot white bread’ (Brown 2010, p. 11).

  29. 29.

    Variants of Reisch’s figure appear in many sixteenth century texts and were even used in some phrenological works as late as the early nineteenth century (Clarke and Dewhurst, p. 39).

  30. 30.

    It may be, of course, that this is no more than a typographical convenience. It is, nevertheless, to found in all the later sixteenth-century diagrams.

  31. 31.

    For information about Robert Fludd and the seventeenth century Rosicrucians see Yates 1972.

  32. 32.

    See Clayton 1992.

  33. 33.

    O’Malley and Saunders 1983, p. 338. Leonardo goes on to instance the attempts of Alchemists to turn lead into gold and the endeavours of Necromancers to communicate with the dead as leading only to the poor-house.

  34. 34.

    Letter, 1639.

  35. 35.

    In the first (1638) edition Plempius strongly disputed Harvey’s theory of the circulation of the blood. By the time of the second (1649) and third (1654) editions he had, however, revised his opinion and become a strong supporter of the Harveyan theory. By this time he had fallen out with Descartes and included an appendix in which three theologians asserted that Descartes’ philosophy was incompatible with the Faith and that his system of medicine was dangerous to health.

  36. 36.

    Britol-Heperides 1990.

  37. 37.

    Lokhorst and Kaitaro (2001) who have made a careful study of Descartes’ sources conclude that his pineal theory is largely original with him.

  38. 38.

    Coleridge, Philosophical Lectures, 1818–1819: ‘Descartes was the man who made Nature utterly lifeless... and considered it as a subject for purely mechanical laws’. See Coburn 1949, pp. 376–378.

  39. 39.

    In a letter to his much admired Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia he writes that it is a waste of life to spend too much time over the problem (Descartes, June, 1643: in Anscombe and Geach 1954, p. 282).

  40. 40.

    See Smith 1998.

  41. 41.

    Augustine, De civitate Dei, 10, 26.

  42. 42.

    Kenny 1970, p. 83.

  43. 43.

    Quoted Crombie, 1959, vol. 2, p. 86.

  44. 44.

    Descartes 1633/1662, trs Hall, p. 202.

  45. 45.

    See Chaps. 16, 17 and 18, this volume.

References

  • Albert the Great (2008) Questions concerning Aristotle’s “On Animals”. In: Resnick IM, Kitchell KF (trans) The Fathers of the Church, mediaeval continuation. Catholic University of America Press, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe E, Geach PT (1954) Descartes: philosophical writings. Nelson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon F (1620) Sylva Sylvarum, unpublished mss

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon R, Bridges JH (1897) The Opus Majus of Roger Bacon, 2 vols. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bardy G (1953) St Augustine et les médecins. L’Année Théologique Augustinienne 13:327–346

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauhin C (1605, 1st edn, 1621, 2nd edn) Theatrum anatomicum. Mattaei Bekeripp, Frankfurt

    Google Scholar 

  • Britol-Heperides A (1990) Le Principe de vie chez Descartes. Vrin, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown A (2010) The return of Lucretius to Renaissance Florence. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke E, Dewhurst K (1972) An illustrated history of brain function. Sandford Publications, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton M (1992) Leonardo da Vinci: the anatomy of man. Museum of Fine Arts and Bullfinch Press, Houston

    Google Scholar 

  • Coburn K (1949) Philosophical lectures of Samuel Taylor Coleridge. Pilot Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin E (1801) Zoonomia; or the laws or organic life, 3rd edn. J. Johnson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes (1633/1662) De homine. Leiden; Hall TS (trans) (1972) Treatise of man. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Furley DJ, Wilkie JS (1984) Galen on Respiration and the Arteries: an Edition with English Translation and Commentary of De usu respirationis, An in arteriis natura sanguis contineatur. De usu pulsuum, and De causis respirationis. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Galen. On the natural faculties; trans. Brock AJ (1916) Heinemann, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Galen. De usu partium corporis humani [On the usefulness of the parts of the body]; trans. May MT (1968) Cornell University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny A (1970) Descartes: philosophical letters. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lokhorst G-J, Kaitaro TT (2001) The originality of Descartes’ theory about the Pineal Gland. J Hist Neurosci 10:6–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzoni T (1998) The cerebral ventricles, the animal spirits and the dawn of brain localisation of function. Arch Ital Biol 136:103–152

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr D (1976) Early processing of visual information. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 275:483–524

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Daley G (1987) Augustine’s philosophy of mind. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley CD, Saunders JB (1983) Leonardo on the human body. Dover Publications, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel RE (1968) Galen’s system of physiology and medicine. Karger, Basle

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharples RW, Van der Eijk P (2008) Nemesius: on the nature of man. Liverpool University Press, Liverpool

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith CUM (1998) Descartes’ visit to the town library, or how Augustinian is Descartes’ neurophysiology? J Hist Neurosci 7:93–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith CUM (2005) All from fibres: Erasmus Darwin’s evolutionary psychobiology. In: Smith CUM, Arnott R (eds) The genius of Erasmus Darwin. Ashgate, Aldershot, pp 133–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith CUM, Frixione E, Finger S, Clower W (2012) The animal spirit doctrine and the origins of neurophysiology. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • St. Augustine. De quantitate animae. In: de Labriolle P (ed and trans) (1948) Oeuvres de Saint Augustine, vol 5, Études Augustininennes. Desclée de Brouwer, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • St Augustine. De genesi ad litteram. In: Agäesse P, Solignac A (ed and trans) (1972) Oeuvres de Saint Augustine, vols. 48, 49, Études Augustinennes. Desclée de Brouwer, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • St Augustine. De civitate Dei; Healey J (trans) (1931) The city of God. Dent, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Willis T (1681) The anatomy of the brain and nerves, facsimile edition of Cerebri Anatome. Englished by S. Pordage, edited by W. Feindel (1965) McGill University Press, Montreal

    Google Scholar 

  • Yates F (1972) The Rosicrucian enlightenment. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to C. U. M. Smith .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Smith, C.U.M. (2014). Beginnings: Ventricular Psychology. In: Smith, C., Whitaker, H. (eds) Brain, Mind and Consciousness in the History of Neuroscience. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 6. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-8774-1_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics