Skip to main content

The Core of the Methodological Question: Procedure, Rules, Classifications

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Methodological Misconceptions in the Social Sciences
  • 641 Accesses

Abstract

Here we set out in full our methodological proposal for the study of social reality, taking care to emphasize the organizational aspect, which represents the basic feature of society. A core step in the proposed deductive procedure is the selection of realistic postulates or, more specifically, the definition of guiding rules for such a selection and a classification of postulates that allows for: (a) the achievement of general principles despite the non-repetitive changes that impede upon social reality; (b) the derivation of more specific organizational features. In particular, the notions of functional and ontological imperatives are specified; notions that, together with that of civilization, express the organizational backbone and, in interaction with specific choices, innovation and creativeness, the leading forces of social processes. This specification allows some conceptual development concerning the roles of a number of factors: freedom and constriction, function and conflict, micro and macro aspects, the problem of forecasting and, to some degree, also the vicissitudes of economic and social planning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Long lasting discussions and controversies on axioms and postulates have agitated logical-formal sciences notwithstanding these sciences need, by their nature, a very limited number of postulates. The situation with regard to postulates is much more complicated when deductive procedure is applied in the social sciences; nevertheless, these sciences have dedicated little attention to the question of postulates.

  2. 2.

    See Albert (2012 [1963]), Kapeller (2013).

  3. 3.

    C.S. Peirce underlined the sterility of induction as a supposed seed of creativity, as well as the conservative inclination of logical deduction. He added, therefore, a third category to induction and deduction that he termed “abduction”, which concerned creative formulation of explanatory hypotheses. But this new category has not generated any elaboration on method that facilitates creativity in formulating theoretical hypotheses. The role that Peirce attributes to metaphor in this regard must be considered with great caution; in fact, and as pointed out above, methods elaborated by other sciences are completely inappropriate to social research.

  4. 4.

    Note that structural change due to creativity impedes the use of conventional modeling and stability analysis, i.e. analysis based on a precise quantitative structure from which are derived eigenvectors and which allow the development of quali-quantitative analyses of the effects of changes in parameters.

  5. 5.

    See Parsons (1987) and Parsons and Smelser (1964).

  6. 6.

    Of course, abstracting also from the particular conditions of nature.

  7. 7.

    For instance, and as we shall see in the paragraph on exemplification, Kirzner’s analysis of economic process implicitly specifies (and is hinged on) some basic functional imperatives of modern dynamic economies (the entrepreneur, market process, decentralization of decision making). Again, Williamson’s analysis centered on transaction costs, as well as the economic analysis of rights (EAR), are substantially aimed at pointing out that the firm’s organization and some rights represent functional imperatives.

  8. 8.

    The results presented in this and the previous paragraph may provide a substantial contribution to the solution of the “post positivist puzzle of relativism” and the incommensurability problem, pointed out by Ardebili (2003). R. Bhaskar’s solution here is not exhaustive since it eludes the ontology of science, i.e. “the scientists’ conception of reality”.

  9. 9.

    Such powers might be substituted by forms of imperialism; but these are strongly opposed by the conscience of modern Man.

  10. 10.

    See (Ekstedt and Fusari 2010), chapter 8.

  11. 11.

    For instance, a desert people and a seafaring people will be induced by their differing environmental circumstances to construct dissimilar institutions and social orders. Institutional and organizational dissimilarities will also mark the social systems of peoples with – for example – different religious beliefs and/or different technological conditions.

  12. 12.

    It should be noted that the term civilization as so defined means something different than does the term culture. Even when this latter term is taken in the wide sense attributed to it by anthropologists, the notion of civilization just given is, still, the wider and more stringent one. Of particular importance, the term civilization as so defined expresses better than the term culture the imprinting of what I have called ‘grand options’ upon the basic features of the social system, side by side with the other basic organizational categories that I denominate functional and ontological imperatives, and avoids mixing with these categories.

  13. 13.

    Naturally, the two types interact; indeed, the same innovation may belong to both categories. Other types of innovations, such as radical and incremental ones, should be considered; they play a crucial role in economic modeling (see, for instance, Fusari and Reati 2013; Ekstedt and Fusari 2010).

  14. 14.

    For example, it must be ascertained that the value premises adopted constitute a consistent set, headed by supreme ideals, followed by some other general value premises and, still further down, specific value premises. In other words, each norm must be coherent with the overarching system of ideals.

  15. 15.

    Such an invariant structure permits quali-quantitative mathematical analyses directed to investigate the existence of equilibrium, its stability or to point out the existence of strange attractors shaping chaotic areas.

  16. 16.

    See Pasinetti (1993), p. 49.

  17. 17.

    The European Association for Evolutionary Political Economy (EAEPE) provides one of the best instances of the attempt to marry evolutionary and institutional thought. This is expressed well, for example, in the convergence of the institutionalism of G. M. Hodgson and the social evolutionism of U. Witt.

  18. 18.

    F. Archibugi has argued acutely against positive economics. His emphasis on the ‘programmatic approach’ highlights the most relevant tools on optimal planning. But this kind of constructivism, which emphasizes doing and almost forgets being and ignores the distinction between ‘necessity’ and ‘choice-possibility’, expresses a totally unilateral constructivist feature, which is the main reason for the failure of the method of economic and social planning. See (Archibugi 2007), Preliminary draft, Italian.

  19. 19.

    See, Ruffolo (1973) Rapporto sulla programmazione, Laterza, Bari.

References

  • Albert, H. (2012 [1963]). Model Platonism: Neoclassical economic thought in critical light (translated by D. Arnold and F. P. Maier-Rigaud). Journal of Institutional Economics, 8(3), 295–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archibugi, F. (2002). L’economia associativa. Sguardi oltre il Welfare State e nel post-capitalismo. Turin: Edizioni di Comunità.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archibugi, F. (2007). The end of economics. An anti-positivist manifesto in a post-economic perspective. Preliminary draft, Italian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ardebili, M. H. (2003). Is there a future for heterodox economics? An argument for pluralism and integration. Paper presented at the ICAPE conference on the future of heterodox economics, Kansas City, MI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnsperger, C. (2007). Critical political economy. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berardi, G. G. (1964). Class and class conflicts. The sociologic inheritance of Marx (pp. 1–67). Rome: Cultura e scuola.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blaug, M. (1980). The methodology of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boulding, K. E. (1970). Economics as a science. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brody, T. (1994). The philosophy behind physics. Berlin/Heidelberg/New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callon, M. (Ed.). (1998). The laws of the market. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cockett, R. (1994). Thinking the unthinkable: Think Tanks and the economic counterrevolution, 1931–1983. London: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coser, L. A. (1967). The functions of social conflict. Milan: Feltrinelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahrendorf, R. (1963). Class and class conflict in industrial society. Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, J. B. (2003). The theory of the individual in economics. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dobb, M. (1974). On economic theory and socialism. Rome: Editori Riuniti.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekstedt, H., & Fusari, A. (2010). Economic theory and social change. Problems and revisions. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, R. (1976). Economic planning studies. Selected and introduced by Frank Long. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frish, R. (1965). Theory of production. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fusari, A. (1977). The role of demand in the contemporary economy. Economia & Lavoro, (3), 407–428, and in La Teoria Keynesiana quarant’anni dopo (Società Italiana degli Economisti, Ed.). Milan: Giuffrè Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fusari, A. (1987). A development model of a dualistic economy: The Italian case. In B. Martos, L. P. Pau, & M. Ziermann (Eds.), Dynamic modelling and control of national economics (IFAC proceeding series 1987). Oxford/New York/Sydney/Tokio/Toronto: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fusari, A. (1992). Entrepreneurship, market process and economic development. Some theoretical and empirical insights useful for managing the transition period. In W. Owsinski, J. Stefanski, & A. Straszak (Eds.), Transition to advanced market economies (pp. 255–268). The Association of Polish Operational Research Societies, Warsaw.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fusari, A. (1996). Paths of economic development: Modelling factors of endogenous growth. International Journal of Social Economics, 23(10/11), 164–191. http://dx.doi.org/10.1108/03068299610149525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fusari, A. (2004). A reconsideration on the method of economic and social sciences. Procedure, rules, classifications. International Journal of Social Economics, 31(5/6), 501–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fusari, A., & Reati, A. (2013). Endogenizing technical change: Uncertainty, profits, entrepreneurship. Structural Change and Economic Dynamics’ (SCED), 24, 76–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerschenkron, A. (1952). Economic backwardness in historical perspective. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grebel, T., Hanusch, H., & Pyka, A. (2001). An evolutionary approach to the theory of entrepreneurship. In EAEPE conference of Siena.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1949). Individualism and economic order. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A. (1974). Imperialism. A study. London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G. M. (2001). How economics forgot history. The problem of historical specificity in social science. London/New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kapeller, J. (2013). ‘Model-Platonism’ in economics: On a classical epistemological critique. Journal of Institutional Economics, 9(2), 199–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirzner, M. I. (1973). Competition and entrepreneurship. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klant, J. J. (1994). The nature of economic thought. Aldershot: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, A. (1998). Studies in scientific realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (2003). Reorienting economics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, K. (1977). Il Capitale. Roma: Editori Riuniti.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, J. G. (1978). Living systems. New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgenbesser, S. (1969). The realist-instrumentalist controversy. In S. Mergenbesser, P. Suppes, & M. White (Eds.), Philosophy, science and method (pp. 200–218). New York: St Martein’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgenstern, O. (1955). Studi di metodologia economica. Milan: Editrice L’Industria.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1981). Unreal assumptions in economic theory: The F-twist untwisted. Kyklos, 34(3), 377–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, R. R., & Winter, S. G. (1982). An evolutionary theory of economic change. Cambridge, MA/London: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ollman, B. (Ed.). (1998). Market socialism. The debate among socialists. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto, V. (1974). Manuale di economia politica. Padova: CEDAM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1987). The structure of social action. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T., & Smelser, N. J. (1964). Economy and society. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pasinetti, L. L. (1993). Structural economic dynamics. A theory of the economic consequences of human learning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peart, S., & Levy, D. (2005). The ‘vanity of the philosopher’: From equality to hierarchy in post-classical economics. Ann Harbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1966). The tacit dimension. Garden City: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1980). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchison.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1938). Experience and prediction. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruffolo, G. (1973). Rapporto sulla programmazione. Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Runciman, W. G. (1972). Economy and society. A study on the integration of economic and social theory. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russel, B. (1992). The principles of mathematics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saviotti, P. P. (1996). Technological evolution, variety and the economy. Cheltenham: E. Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter, J. A. (1994). History of economic analysis. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2002). Rationality and freedom. Harvard: Belknap.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1983). Reason in human affairs. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1957). Introduction to logic. Princeton: Nostrand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen, J. (1964). Central planning. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veblen, T. (1967). Absentee ownership and business enterprise in recent times. The case of America. With an introduction by Robert Leckachman. Boston: Beacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, L. (1946). Economic calculus in the socialist state. In F. A. Hayek (Ed.), Economic collectivist planning. Turin: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1974). The method of the social-historical sciences. Torino: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weintraub, E. R. (1979). Microfoundations: The compatibility of microeconomic and macroeconomic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O. E. (1981, December). The modern corporation: Origins, evolution, attributes. Journal of Economic Literature, XIX, 1537–1568.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zamagni, S. (1987). Microeconomic theory. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zamagni, S., Scazzieri, R., & Sen, A. (2008). Markets, money and history. Essays in honor of Sir J. Hicks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Angelo Fusari .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fusari, A. (2014). The Core of the Methodological Question: Procedure, Rules, Classifications. In: Methodological Misconceptions in the Social Sciences. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-8675-1_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics