Skip to main content

Human Rights and Human Animals

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 35))

Abstract

In his paper Human Rights and Human Animals, Bernd Ladwig assumes that whoever seeks to provide justifying reasons for human rights seems to be, in some way or another, committed to universal anthropological claims. Nonetheless, as Ladwig argues, it is clear that anthropology alone cannot provide sufficient grounds for human rights. In addition to an anthropological footing, we also need recourse to at least one valid moral principle—and, thus, to a source of reasons that cannot be derived solely from empirical claims about human nature. In his paper, Ladwig merely argues, therefore, that some anthropological arguments are necessary to justify some of the specific contents of human rights. To that end, he portrays humans as a special sort of animal endowed with two natures. This anthropological approach provides the argumentative framework within which we can derive some, but not all, of the specific contents of human rights, as Ladwig claims.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For an example, see Wilson (2002); against the reductionist tendencies in naturalistic approaches such as Wilson’s see Illies (2006).

  2. 2.

    There are, to be sure, phenomena related to cultural fluctuations that do seem to correspond to the model of “memetic” transmission through imitation, for example, fashion. But it is precisely because any particular prevailing fashion is hardly a rationally reconstructable phenomenon that its abrupt disappearance is hardly surprising. The arbitrariness of particular fashions corresponds directly to their unsteadiness.

  3. 3.

    What I mean, in general, here is that any human form of life is confronted with the task of avoiding mistakes, and no form of life could have emerged without a vast number of actions that were based on true, well-grounded beliefs. Moral problems are only a special case of the generalized normative imperative of discovering the right and avoiding the wrong.

  4. 4.

    “Drawing distinctions” and “choosing” are of course not meant in the sense of propositionally reflected modes of interacting with the world, but rather in the sense of knowing how, which we can ascribe to the chimpanzee without also ascribing knowing that.

  5. 5.

    For a critical appraisal, see Jörke (2005, 98f).

  6. 6.

    That is the famous critical example from Nozick (1974, 42–45).

  7. 7.

    See Physicians for Human Rights (1998).

References

  • Birnbacher, D. 2009. Was kann die Anthropologie zur Politik und ihrer theoretischen Fundierung beitragen? In Politische Anthropologie. Geschichte—Gegenwart—Möglichkeiten, ed. D. Jörke and B. Ladwig, 179–194. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackmore, S. 1999. The meme machine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R.B. 1967. Ethical relativism. In Encyclopedia of philosophy, vol. 3, ed. P. Edwards, 75–78. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, D. 1991. Human universals. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 1982. Rational animals. Dialectica 36(3): 317–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, J. 1992. The third chimpanzee: The evolution and future of the human animal. New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1970. The nature and value of rights. Journal of Value Inquiry 4: 243–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forst, R. 2007. The justification of human rights and the basic right to justification: A reflexive approach. Ethics 120(4): 711–740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehlen, A. 1940/1986. Der Mensch. Seine Natur und seine Stellung in der Welt, Gesamtausgabe Bd. 3. Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gert, B. 1998. Morality: Its nature and justification. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. 1981. Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns. Bd. 1, Handlungsrationalität und gesellschaftliche Rationalisierung. Frankfurt a. M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampshire, S. 1983. Morality and conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Höffe, O. 1998. Transzendentaler Tausch. Eine Legitimationsfigur für Menschenrechte? In Philosophie der Menschenrechte, ed. St. Gosepath and G. Lohmann, 29–47. Frankfurt a. M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illies, C. 2006. Philosophische Anthropologie im biologischen Zeitalter, Zur Konvergenz von Moral und Natur. Frankfurt a. M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jörke, D. 2005. Politische Anthropologie. Eine Einführung. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kekes, J. 1994. Pluralism and the value of life. In Cultural pluralism and moral knowledge, ed. E. Fraenkel Paul, F.D. Miller, and J. Paul, 44–60. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladwig, B. 2007a. Menschenrechte und menschliche Natur. Bausteine zu einer kritischen Theorie der Menschenrechte. Leviathan—Berliner Zeitschrift für Sozialwissenschaften 35: 85–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladwig, B. 2007b. Das Recht auf Leben—nicht nur für Personen. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 55: 17–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 1996. Two sorts of naturalism. In Virtues and reasons. Philippa foot and moral theory, ed. R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence, and W. Quinn, 149–179. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. 1887/1967. On the genealogy of morals. In “On the genealogy of morals” and “Ecce Homo”, Trans. and ed. W. Kaufmann. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M.C. 1993. Non-relative virtues: An Aristotelian approach. In The quality of life, ed. M.C. Nussbaum and A. Sen, 242–269. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M.C. 2006. Frontiers of justice. Disability. Nationality. Species membership. Cambridge, MA/London: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Physicians for Human Rights. 1998. The Taliban’s war on women: A health and human rights crisis in Afghanistan. http://physiciansforhumanrights.org/library/reports/talibans-war-on-women-1998.html. Last download on 6 Feb 2013.

  • Plessner, H. 1927/1981. Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch. Einleitung in die philosophische Anthropologie. Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, Th. 2002. World poverty and human rights. Cosmopolitan principles and reforms. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1990. Realism with a human face. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1993. Objectivity and the science-ethics distinction. In The quality of life, ed. M.C. Nussbaum and A. Sen, 143–157. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. 1993. Human rights, rationality, and sentimentality. In On human rights: The 1993 Oxford Amnesty lectures, ed. S. Hurley and St. Shute. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. 1995. The construction of social reality. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seel, M. 1995. Versuch über die Form des Glücks. Studien zur Ethik. Frankfurt a. M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 1999. The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tugendhat, E. 2007. Anthropologie als ‘Erste Philosophie‘. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 55: 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E.O. 2002. Sociobiology: The new synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, U. 1986. Was es heißt, sein Leben zu leben. Philosophische Rundschau 33: 242–265.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bernd Ladwig .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ladwig, B. (2014). Human Rights and Human Animals. In: Albers, M., Hoffmann, T., Reinhardt, J. (eds) Human Rights and Human Nature. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 35. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-8672-0_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics