Skip to main content

Xunzi Among the Chinese Neo-Confucians

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Dao Companion to the Philosophy of Xunzi

Part of the book series: Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy ((DCCP,volume 7))

Abstract

This chapter explains how Xunzi’s text and views helped shape the thought of the Neo-Confucian philosophers, noting and explicating some areas of influence long overlooked in modern scholarship. It begins with a general overview of Xunzi’s changing position in the tradition (“Xunzi’s Status in Neo-Confucian Thought”), in which I discuss Xunzi’s status in three general periods of Neo-Confucian era: the early period, in which Neo-Confucian views of Xunzi were varied and somewhat ambiguous, the “mature” period, in which a broad consensus formed and then became orthodoxy for several centuries, and a late and often overlooked reassessment of Xunzi that took place in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. In the second section (“Debating Human Nature on Xunzi’s Terms”), I discuss in greater detail Neo-Confucian criticisms of Xunzi’s views on human nature, noting that in key respects the Neo-Confucians accepted Xunzi’s somewhat uncharitable characterization of the doctrine that human nature is good, thereby taking on a considerably greater burden of proof than necessary. In the third section (“Virtue without Roots”), I attempt to explicate what is perhaps the most prominent but also the most laconic Neo-Confucian criticism of Xunzi, which is that Xunzi misunderstands the “great root” or “great foundation” of cosmic and social order, finding it in conventional human relationships rather than in the deeper, purer and more powerful inner workings of human nature. In the final section (“The Accretional Theory of Knowledge Acquisition”), I explain how the major differences between Xunzi and his Neo-Confucian critics can be cast as a dispute about how moral knowledge is acquired, where Xunzi’s critics assume that acquiring moral knowledge of any meaningful kind is impossible without a natural base or foundation of moral knowledge to begin with.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Yang (1965: chapter 3, 10–11). For a translation see Chan (1963: 289–90).

  2. 2.

    See his “Inquiry into Human Nature” 原性 in Han (1968: 6b–7a). For a translation see Tiwald and Van Norden (2014: 132–33).

  3. 3.

    “Pattern” is also a common and perhaps, in this case, more informative translation, but in the interest of using the terminology consistently across this volume, I will adopt the more familiar translation as “principle.” Another translation, “coherence,” usefully captures the idea that each manifestation of the li forms an intelligible and harmonious whole with the others, but this fact should not be seen as reason to downplay the robust metaphysical commitments implicit in the idea of a subtle, metaphysical pattern that underlies all phenomena. See Angle (2009: 31–50 and 2011) and Tiwald (2011a, b).

  4. 4.

    See Zhou’s Tongshu 通書 (“Penetrating the Book of Changes”) (Zhou 1990: section 7, 19 and section 22, 30). For translations see Chan (1963: 468, 474). The one passage that scholars take as direct evidence that Zhou believed human nature to be good is his discussion of cheng 誠 (“sincerity” or “integrity”) in the same work (Zhou 1990: section 1, 12; Chan 1963: 465–66). A.C. Graham makes a compelling argument against this reading of the passage in Graham (1992: 60, n. 42).

  5. 5.

    Mengzi 7B35, modified from Van Norden 2008 to reflect Zhou’s interpretation.

  6. 6.

    See the opening section of Zhou’s Zazhu 雜著 (“Miscellaneous Writings”) in Zhou (1990: 52).

  7. 7.

    See Cheng and Cheng (1981: juan 1, 10–11). For a translation see Chan (1963: 528).

  8. 8.

    Tan mei zhi ci 歎美之辭.

  9. 9.

    Zhu 1965: juan 42, 6a. Chen Lai’s 陳來 interpretation of the passage is typical. He infers that for Hu the character shan (good) is best suited to express admiration in matters of human ethics or the ethics of social and interpersonal relationships, which does not account for the greatness of nature as foundation and harmonizer of the cosmos (Chen 2010: 177–78).

  10. 10.

    Cheng , following Zhang Zai 張載 (1020–1077 CE), called the ordinary kind “material nature ” or “psycho-physical nature” (qizhi zhi xing 氣質之性) and the more profound kind by various names, especially “original nature” (ben xing 本性 ) and “the nature of Heaven and Earth” (Tiandi zhi xing 天地之性).

  11. 11.

    Cheng and Cheng (1981: juan 18, 204 and juan 24, 322). For a translation of the first of these passages see Chan (1963: 567).

  12. 12.

    Da ben 大本.

  13. 13.

    Zhu (1986: 4.92/77–78, 59.55/1389, 137.12/3254, 137.70/3273). In this chapter, I cite sections of The Topically Arranged Conversations of Master Zhu (Zhuzi yulei 朱子語類) by juan and paragraph number, and then the page number in the Zhonghua shuju edition. For example, the first passage cited here—4.92/77–78—appears in juan 4, paragraph 92, pages 77–78.

  14. 14.

    Zhu (1986: 35.109/932), referencing the first chapter of the Xunzi (“An Exhortation to Learning”). In this chapter, I will cite specific passages from the Xunzi by the numbering in Lau and Chen 1996, labeled here as “HKCS”), and then page number in Hutton’s translation (2014), labeled here as “H.” For example, the passage cited appears in chapter 1, page 3, and line 20 in Lau and Chen 1996, and page 6 in Hutton 2014. As such, it is abbreviated as “HKCS 1/3/20, H 6.” For another passage praising Xunzi on the concrete details of moral cultivation see Zhu (1986: 10.61/169), referencing Xunzi, HKCS 1/4/16-17, H 8. The second of these remarks by Zhu is translated in Gardner (1990: 136). See also Zhu (1986: 95.127/2447 and 137.10/3253), where Zhu approves of Xunzi’s discussion of the characteristic attitudes of great- and small-hearted gentlemen (da xin 大心 and xiao xin 小心) (Xunzi, HKCS 3/10/6, H 18).

  15. 15.

    Zhu (1986: 137.67/3272). Eric Hutton has pointed out that this may be a play on Xunzi’s own language likening our initial reaction to the Way to a person’s reaction to meats and fine rice after a lifetime of eating rice dregs (Xunzi, HKCS 4/15/17-21, H 28). The Neo-Confucians’ fascination with complex metaphysical and cosmological worldviews seems to have few parallels in Xunzi. One scholar who nevertheless thinks the Neo-Confucians might have been inspired by some of the Xunzi’s passing cosmological claims is Dai Junren 戴君仁 , who finds parallels between the Neo-Confucians cosmology and some quasi-Daoist remarks in chapter 31 (“Duke Ai”). However, Dai also doubts that this chapter was written by Xunzi himself (1980: vol. II, 1335).

  16. 16.

    However, one specialist in Confucianism argues that two of the Four Books—the Great Learning (Daxue 大學) and the Doctrine of the Mean ( Zhongyong 中庸)—came from a scholarly lineage substantially influenced by Xunzi. See Dai Junren 戴君仁 (1980: 833–48, 1021–30).

  17. 17.

    Cai gao 才高.

  18. 18.

    Guo duo 過多

  19. 19.

    Cheng and Cheng (1981: juan 18, 231, juan 19, 262). See also Zhu (1986: 137.10/3253–54).

  20. 20.

    A striking example comes from a thoughtful exchange between Cheng Yi and a student (Cheng and Cheng 1981: juan 18, 191). There, the student asks Cheng about a respected interpretation of the Doctrine of the Mean ( Zhongyong 中庸), which holds that people can “gradually attain” (xun zhi 馴致) an imperceptible Dao through inward vigilance and caution. In Cheng’s response to the student, he glosses the phrase “gradually attain” (xun zhi) as “gradually advance” or “draw near [to the good] by soaking oneself [in its presence]” (jian jin 漸進), a play on words and artful reference to Xunzi’s “Encouraging Learning” (HKCS 1/1/20 – 1/2/1, H 2–3). The ensuing discussion assumes that the student (and readers of the dialogue) will know much about the specific program of self-cultivation that Xunzi recommends in that chapter.

  21. 21.

    See Zhu (1986: 78.136/2002).

  22. 22.

    Although the Neo-Confucians correctly saw Xunzi as holding that highly virtuous officials contribute tremendously to successful governance, they did not have a clear consensus about whether Xunzi thought the ruler himself needed to be highly virtuous. In part, this was because they were not sure what to make of Xunzi’s proposal that some hegemons (ba 霸) could substitute for a true king when the latter was out of reach. In this respect their uncertainty closely approximates the uncertainty that Eirik L. Harris finds in contemporary literature on Xunzi and the hegemons (see Harris’ essay in this volume).

  23. 23.

    You zhi ren wu zhi fa 有治人無治法. Xunzi, HKCS 12/57/3, H 117. For example, see Hu (1987: 8.18).

  24. 24.

    You zhi fa er hou you zhi ren 有治法而後有治人. See Huang (1965: 6). For a translation, see de Bary (1993: 99) or Tiwald and Van Norden (2014: 318). Although many Neo-Confucians held Xunzi’s political thought in high regard, most also took it to be contaminated by ideas that had come to him (inadvertently) from early Legalist philosophers like Shen Buhai 申不害 (d. 337 BCE) and Shang Yang 商鞅 (390–338 BCE). According to Zhu Xi, this came about because Xunzi advocated for modeling government policies not just on the remote practices of the most ancient sage kings like Yao and Shun, but also on the Houwang 後王 (“Later Kings,” likely the Western Zhou rulers). Xunzi found the accounts of the later kings both reliable and more expedient for historical investigation (Xunzi HKCS 5/18/18-22, H 35–36), but Zhu apparently believed the accounts were corrupted by (and hard to extricate from) Legalist theories popular at the time. See Zhu’s preface to the poem “Chengxiang” 成相, no. 1, in his Chuci jizhu 楚辭集注 (“Collected Commentaries on the Chuci”) (2010: 223–24).

  25. 25.

    This period witnessed tremendous advances in philological techniques and resources, which the most accomplished Confucian scholars frequently used to overturn longstanding Neo-Confucian readings of the classics (Elman 2001: 93–122).

  26. 26.

    These two figures joined at least a dozen of the major philologists and commentators of this prolific period. The best reconstruction of Xunzi’s revival among these scholars is in Makeham (2003: 287–95).

  27. 27.

    Ji 積.

  28. 28.

    See Dai’s Evidential Analysis of the Meaning of Terms in the Mengzi 孟子字義疏證 (1996: section 25) and Tiwald (2010: 401–6). All citations of specific pages of Dai’s Evidential Analysis will begin with the section number and then page numbers in four standard editions or translations: The Collected Works of Dai Zhen (Dai Zhen ji 戴震集) (Dai 2009), Hu Shi’s 胡適 edition (Dai: 1996), the translation by Ann-ping Chin and Mansfield Freeman (1990), and the translation by John W. Ewell (1990). These will be abbreviated as “Ji,” “Hu,” “Chin,” and “Ewell,” respectively.

  29. 29.

    Dai (1996: section 25, Ji 299, Hu 291, Chin 125, Ewell 169).

  30. 30.

    Zuo wei 作為. The best-known refrain in Xunzi’s discussion of human nature might be translated conventionally as “the goodness [of human beings] is a matter [or product] of artificial activity” (qi shan zhe wei ye 其善者偽也; my emphasis). These nineteenth-century defenders of Xunzi suggested that it should be read instead as saying that human goodness is a matter or product of action, without any implication that the action is artificial or non-natural. For the refrain see Xunzi, HKCS 23/113/3, H 248.

  31. 31.

    This was the position of Jiao Xun 焦循 (1763–1820 CE), best known as the author-commentator of the Correct Meanings of the Mengzi (Mengzi zheng yi 孟子正義). See Jiao’s preface to Mengzi 3A (1987: 316–17) and Makeham (2003: 289, 293–94).

  32. 32.

    This was the view of Liu Baonan 劉寶楠 (1791–1855). See Makeham 2003: 291 and 298–99.

  33. 33.

    Philip J. Ivanhoe makes excellent use of analogies between moral development and language development to illuminate Xunzi’s and Mengzi’s doctrines of human nature. See Ivanhoe (2000b).

  34. 34.

    For just a few examples, see Ivanhoe (2002: 37–46, 57–58), Graham (2002), and Van Norden (2007: 201–11).

  35. 35.

    Slightly modified from Van Norden (2008).

  36. 36.

    Xunzi HKCS 23/113/19 – 23/114/2, H 249–50; Hutton’s translation.

  37. 37.

    “Those things in people that cannot be learned and cannot be worked at are called their ‘nature’” (Xunzi, HKCS 23/113/18, H 249); Hutton’s translation.

  38. 38.

    Xing ben shan 性本善, my emphasis.

  39. 39.

    See Cheng and Cheng (1981: juan 18, 187), and Zhu (1986: 4.57/68, 4.66/72, 6.68/108). For the passage in which Xunzi substitutes ben xing for xing see Xunzi, HKCS 23/115/20–22, H 253.

  40. 40.

    As stated earlier, this leaves room for some additional and more constructive work necessary to access the pre-existing moral insight. For accounts of some of the subtler constructive work as construed by Zhu, see Angle (2009: 161–78) and Van Norden (2007: 47–48).

  41. 41.

    Si 私.

  42. 42.

    Shun 2010: 186–87.

  43. 43.

    Zhu 1986: 4.40/64–65, 59.52/1388.

  44. 44.

    Zhu routinely quotes the following remark by Cheng , reading Cheng’s “nature” as a reference to original nature: “To discuss the nature without discussing qi is incomplete. To discuss qi without discussing the nature is unclear” (論性不論氣, 不備; 論氣不論性, 不明. Cheng and Cheng 1981: juan 6, 81).

  45. 45.

    Zhu 1986: 4.40/64–65, 4.46/67, 4.52/68. As Philip J. Ivanhoe points out, Zhu essentially takes the Buddhist claim that character and perceptual flaws are unreal and substitutes the claim that these flaws are unnatural (Ivanhoe 2000a: 44–45).

  46. 46.

    See Dai (1996: section 27, Ji 303, Hu 298, Chin 132, Ewell 288). A.C. Graham seems to invoke either or both of the second and third reasons (Graham 1992: 44).

  47. 47.

    Zhu and Lü 2008: 1.14, 27–28, translation available in Chan 1967: 1.14, 14–15.

  48. 48.

    Zhu 1986: 59.4/1375, 118.89/2863–64.

  49. 49.

    Jin 近.

  50. 50.

    Xunzi, HKCS 9/39/1–7, H 75–76 (lines 286–315) and HKCS 16/79/7–9, H 173 (lines 381–89).

  51. 51.

    Xunzi, HKCS 9/39/2–6, H 75 (lines 291–306); slightly modified from Hutton’s translation.

  52. 52.

    Cheng and Cheng (1981: juan 19, 262).

  53. 53.

    See Zhu and Lü (2008: 1.3, 20); translation available in Chan (1967: 1.3, 8).

  54. 54.

    The Chinese for these phrases are wu wei 無為 and wu qiang 無彊, respectively.

  55. 55.

    Xunzi, HKCS 21/105/18 – 21/106/1, H 232; Hutton’s translation.

  56. 56.

    See Xunzi HKCS 21/106/3–4, H 232; Hutton’s translation. Kwong-loi Shun highlights a number of shared ocular metaphors in Shun (2010: 180–81).

  57. 57.

    Stalnaker (2003).

  58. 58.

    See Xunzi, HKCS 21/104/3–4, H 228 and Adler (2008).

  59. 59.

    Cai Renhou 蔡仁厚 makes the interesting point that both Xunzi and Zhu Xi see the heart/mind as playing a largely managerial role over the other parts, regulating them in the name of standards that are not of its own making (like a household manager following orders from the head of the household). But there is a stronger sense of the heart/mind’s mastery where it actually serves as both enforcer and source of the regulations it issues (like heads of household themselves). Cai finds this more robust sort of self-mastery not in Zhu’s conception of heart/mind but in his account of our original or moral nature (1987: 10–11, 49).

  60. 60.

    See Xunzi, HKCS 21/105/5-8, H 231. It is likely that Zhu Xi was also struck by the fact that Xunzi cites a passage from the Documents (although slightly altered and attributed to a lost text), which, on Zhu’s reading (but probably not Xunzi’s), suggests that one develops a superior heart/mind through a state of mental equilibrium (zhong 中). See Xunzi, HKCS 21/105/4, H 231, Legge (1970: 60) and Zhu’s preface to the Doctrine of the Mean ( Zhongyong 中庸) in Zhu (1983: 14). Thanks to Eric Hutton for drawing this passage to my attention.

  61. 61.

    Again, see Xunzi’s mirror metaphor for the heart/mind at Xunzi, HKCS 21/105/5–8, H 231.

  62. 62.

    To cite a famous scenario described in Mengzi 2A6.

  63. 63.

    Zhu (1986: 16.86/330–31).

  64. 64.

    Xunzi HKCS 21/104/3–4, H 228; Hutton’s translation.

  65. 65.

    Zhu (1986: 16.86/330–31).

  66. 66.

    Bu cheng 不誠.

  67. 67.

    “Even if one’s behavior is correct one’s thoughts may still conceal some hidden fetters of miserliness. . . . This is how insincere thoughts originate in what Xunzi calls ‘relaxing so that [the heart/mind] can go about on its own’” Zhu (1986: 72.114/1838).

  68. 68.

    Zhu (1986: 72.113/1837).

  69. 69.

    See Zhu and Lü (2008: 1.3, 20); translation available in Chan (1967: 1.3, 8).

  70. 70.

    Zhu 1986: 96.42/2469. Partial translation available in Chan (1967: 146).

  71. 71.

    Zhu’s point is not that we have to maintain the stillness of the heart/mind even as we go about our regular activities, but that the power we access in stillness has to be accessed in active states as well (Zhu and Lü 2008: 4.53, 218–19; translation available in Chan 1967: 4.53, 145–48). This gives Zhu another potential criticism of Xunzi: Xunzi cannot explain how the power inherent in stillness transfers over to one’s judgment in the midst of one’s encounters with external things and events.

  72. 72.

    Wang 2000: section 308; translation modified from Ivanhoe 2002a: 55.

  73. 73.

    Wei ji 為己 and wei ren 為人. Zhu takes these phrases from Analects 14.24.

  74. 74.

    Zhu 1986: 8.80/139; translation by Gardner 1990: 110.

  75. 75.

    Suo guo zhe hua, suo cun zhe shen 所過者化, 所存者神 (Zhu 1986: 60.105/1441). The passage alluded to here appears in Xunzi’s chapter 15, “A Debate on Military Affairs” (HKCS 15/71/24, H 155). Zhu suggests that this was a common expression whose deeper significance Xunzi himself was not alert to. His unmentioned evidence that it was a common expression probably included Mengzi 7A13.

  76. 76.

    Xunzi, HKCS 1/4/16-19, H 8; Hutton’s translation.

  77. 77.

    This is another and perhaps mutually compatible way of reading the passage quoted above. See also Xunzi, HKCS 22/111/14-18, H 244.

  78. 78.

    As Eric Hutton has pointed out to me, this opens Xunzi to another line of criticism from Zhu Xi. Presumably, at some point in a would-be virtuous agent’s moral development, he will cease seeing his behavior (and reasons for that behavior) in non-moral terms and take up a moral point of view. But what accounts for that transition? If there is a story to be told in the Xunzi it is not forthcoming. By contrast, the “great root” helps to explain how the moral point of view is eventually discovered and then adopted as a way of framing one’s thoughts and inclinations.

  79. 79.

    Ming yu xin 明於心.

  80. 80.

    Zide 自得.

  81. 81.

    Dai 1996: section 41, Ji 325–26, Hu 330–31, Chin 169–70, Ewell 396–98.

  82. 82.

    Mengzi’s adversary here is a Mohist who wants to split the difference between impartial care and graded love, allowing that people can form special attachments to family in the early stages but should eventually come to care about all people equally. For more on this (admittedly controversial) reading of the “two roots” passage see Nivison (1996) and Van Norden (2007: 305–12).

  83. 83.

    Biran 必然.

  84. 84.

    Ziran 自然 .

  85. 85.

    Dai 1996: section 15, Ji 285, Hu 270, Chin 100, Ewell 199–200.

  86. 86.

    To this we might add moral requirements more familiar to contemporary moral philosophers, such as the requirement that we forcibly harvest one innocent and healthy person’s organs in order to save the lives of three sick people, or save the life of a stranger’s child in lieu of saving the life of our own. Both of these are moral requirements that seem to follow from a theory that (to put it somewhat crudely) requires us to bring as much good to as many people as possible, which is a rough description of what contemporary philosophers call “consequentialism .” For most of the human species, it would be impossible to so transform ourselves that we could feel at home in systems of moral norms that require such things of us, in large part because they go so strongly against the life-based dispositions that are natural for our species. And insofar as we think these life-based dispositions should set limits to our moral norms, we share common cause with Dai Zhen. For more on contemporary responses to overly demanding moral requirements see Williams (1981) and (1985).

  87. 87.

    Jiao 教.

  88. 88.

    Dai 1996: section 15, Ji 285, Hu 271, Chin 100–101, Ewell 200–201.

  89. 89.

    “[Xunzi] thought ritual propriety and righteousness issue only from the heart/mind of the sage, so that ordinary people must [first] engage in learning and only then can understand ritual propriety and righteousness” (Dai 1996: section 25, Ji 299, Hu 291, Chin 125, Ewell 269).

  90. 90.

    Dai (1996: section 26, Ji 300, Hu 292–93, Chin 126, Ewell 274).

  91. 91.

    Zhu 1986: 49.27/1203.

  92. 92.

    See Lu’s discussion of the expression qiu ze de zhi 求則得之 (“seek it and you shall get it”) in Lu (1965: juan 32, 4b); translation available in Ivanhoe (2009: 91).

  93. 93.

    For a succinct review of various Neo-Confucian accounts of “getting it oneself,” see de Bary 1991: 43–69.

  94. 94.

    See Dai (1996: section 41) and Tiwald (2010: 411). For the Neo-Confucians, the dispute about whether zide is forced or unforced turns on the Neo-Confucians’ interpretation of Mengzi 4B14, where Mengzi says, “The gentleman immerses himself in the Way, wanting to get it himself [zi de zhi 自得之]. Getting it himself, he is at ease with it. Being at ease with it, he relies upon it deeply. Relying upon it deeply, he comes across its source wherever he turns.” The balance of the evidence favors the view that getting it oneself can be forced. The “unforced” interpretation assumes that the reflexive character zi (“self,” “oneself”) is also being used in the sense of “natural” or “spontaneous.” But in the language of Mengzi’s era, it was extremely rare to see zi in this latter sense when located in front of verb-object phrases, as is the case here (de zhi) (Harbsmeier 1981: 197–99).

  95. 95.

    Zhao 召.

  96. 96.

    “Reverence for one’s elders” is jing zhang 敬長. See Zhu (1983: comments on Mengzi 7A15).

  97. 97.

    “Love of life” is huai sheng 懷生.

Bibliography

  • Adler, Joseph A. 2008. “Zhu Xi’s Spiritual Practice as the Basis of His Central Philosophical Concepts.” Dao 7(1): 57–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angle, Stephen C. 2009. Sagehood: The Contemporary Significance of Neo-Confucian Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (An excellent overview of Neo-Confucianism that accomplishes the formidable task of showing how the orthodox Neo-Confucian philosophers have much significance for contemporary philosophy.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Angle, Stephen C. 2011. “Reply to Justin Tiwald.” Dao 10(2): 237–39. (Angle’s contribution to a debate with Justin Tiwald about the proper translation of li 理, defending “Coherence” over “principle” or “pattern.”)

    Google Scholar 

  • Berthrong, John. 2014. “Xunzi and Zhu Xi.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 40(3–4): 400–16. (A stimulating discussion of some thematic similarities between Xunzi and Zhu Xi, focusing on their use of the character li 理 and their conceptions of the heart/mind.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cai, Renhou 蔡仁厚. 1987. A Comparative Study of “Xin” and “Xing” in the Philosophy of Xunzi and Zhuzi 荀子與朱子: 心性論之比較. Singapore: Institute of East Asian Philosophies. (The only systematic comparison of Xunzi with a leading figure in orthodox Neo-Confucianism. Most notably, Cai argues that Xunzi and Zhu Xi have the same basic conception of heart/mind, one that essentially sees it as an epistemic mechanism that lacks any intrinsic moral proclivities.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, Wing-tsit. 1963. A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (One of the most comprehensive collections of translations of primary texts in Neo-Confucianism, although it also covers other schools and periods. Elements of the translation are dated and the translator uses Wade-Giles rather than pinyin Romanization.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, Wing-tsit. 1967. Reflections on Things at Hand: The Neo-Confucian Anthology, Compiled by Chu Hsi [ Zhu Xi] and Tsu-Ch’ien [ Zuqian]. New York: Columbia University Press. (A complete translation of the Jin si lu 近思錄, a collection of essays and short lessons selected from the work of four 11th century founders of orthodox Neo-Confucianism. The book became the standard introduction to Neo-Confucianism for several centuries of aspiring Confucian scholars, in some respects like a textbook.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Lai 陳來. 2010. The Tradition of Li-Learning in the Song and Ming Dynasties 宋明理學. Taipei 臺北: Yunchen wenhua 允晨文化. (An overview of major themes and concepts in orthodox Neo-Confucianism, by one of the most careful and informed contemporary specialists on Neo-Confucianism.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, Hao 程顥, and Cheng Yi 程頤. 1981 (2008 reprint). “Surviving Works of the Chengs of Henan” 河南程氏遺書. In The Collected Works of the Two Chengs 二程集, ed. Wang Xiaoyu 王孝魚, vol. 1, 1–349, Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局. (The most widely read primary text on the Cheng brothers, presenting short lessons and remarks recorded by their students.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chin, Ann-ping, and Freeman, Mansfield. 1990. Tai Chen on Mencius: Explorations in Words and Meanings. New Haven: Yale University Press. (A complete English translation of Dai Zhen’s masterwork, “Evidential Analysis of the Meaning of Terms in the Mengzi 孟子字義疏證.” Unfortunately the translation has numerous flaws and uses Wade-Giles Romanization rather than pinyin.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dai, Junren 戴君仁. 1980. The Complete Collection of the Works of Mister Dai Jingshan [Dai Junren] 戴靜山先生全集. Taipei 台北: Dai gu zhiyuan 戴顧志鵷. (Includes helpful historical and textual studies of the philosophical language and concepts that might have made their way from Xunzi [or his disciples] into Neo-Confucian discourse.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dai, Zhen 戴震. 1996. “Evidential Analysis of the Meaning of Terms in the Mengzi” 孟子字義疏證. In The Philosophy of Dai Dongyuan 戴東原的哲學, by Hu Shi 胡適, 240–337. Reprinted in Taibei 台北: Taiwan shang wu yin shu guan 臺灣商務印書館. (Dai Zhen’s philosophical masterwork, presented as a critique of the orthodox Neo-Confucians’ reading of the Confucian canon.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dai, Zhen 戴震. 2009. “Evidential Analysis of the Meaning of Terms in the Mengzi” 孟子字義疏證. In The Collected Works of Dai Zhen 戴震集, 263–329. Shanghai 上海: Shanghai guji chubanshe 上海古籍出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Bary, Wm. Theodore. 1991. Learning for One’s Self: Essays on the Individual in Neo-Confucian Thought. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Bary, Wm. Theodore. 1993. Waiting for the Dawn: A Plan for the Prince. New York: Columbia University Press. (A high quality English translation of Huang Zongxi’s Mingyi daifang lu 明夷待訪錄, a work best known for making a compelling case for political and institutional reform.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Elman, Benjamin A. 2001. From Philosophy to Philology: Intellectual and Social Aspects of Change in Late Imperial China (revised). Los Angeles: UCLA Asia-Pacific Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ewell, John W. 1990. “Reinventing the Way: Dai Zhen’s ‘Evidential Commentary on the Meanings of Terms in Mencius’ (1777).” PhD diss., University of California, Berkeley. (A complete English translation of Dai Zhen’s masterwork, “Evidential Analysis of the Meaning of Terms in the Mengzi” 孟子字義疏證. (More accurate than the Chin and Freeman translation listed above. Uses pinyin Romanization.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, Daniel K. 1990. Learning to Be a Sage: Selections from the Conversations of Master Chu, Arranged Topically. Berkeley: University of California Press. (An expert translation of selections from Zhu Xi’s Zhuzi yulei 朱子語類, also known as the Topically Arranged Conversations of Master Zhu. The selections focus on learning.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, A.C. 1992. Two Chinese Philosophers: The Metaphysics of the Brothers Cheng. LaSalle: Open Court. (The best book-length resource on Cheng Hao and Cheng Yi, offering extensive translations and discussion of their views.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, A.C. 2002. “The Background of the Mencian Theory of Human Nature.” In Liu and Ivanhoe (2002): 1–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Han, Yu 韓愈. 1968. “Inquiry into Human Nature” 原性. In The Collected Works of Mister Changli 昌黎先生集, vol. 1, juan 11, 5b–8a. Taipei 臺北: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局 (Sibu beiyao edition). (An important essay by a Tang dynasty forerunner to orthodox Neo-Confucianism, one who shares the orthodox Neo-Confucians’ suspicions of Buddhism but not their robust cosmological and metaphysical framework.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Harbsmeier, Christoph. 1981. Aspects of Classical Chinese Syntax. London: Curzon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hu, Hong 胡宏. 1987. The Collected Works of Hu Hong 胡宏集. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局. (Hu Hong is not widely read but was nevertheless an insightful Neo-Confucian thinker in the lineage of the Cheng brothers. His influence was eventually eclipsed by Zhu Xi, who took issue with several of Hu’s philosophical positions.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hu, Shi 胡適. 1996. The Philosophy of Dai Dongyuan 戴東原的哲學. Reprinted in Taibei 台北: Taiwan shang wu yin shu guan 臺灣商務印書館. (An important but somewhat dated book on Dai Zhen, with substantial appendices that include some of Dai’s philosophical letters and his two most important philosophical works, “On the Good” and the “Evidential Analysis of the Meaning of Terms in the Mengzi.”)

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Zongxi 黃宗羲. 1965. “On Law” 原法. In Waiting for the Dawn 明夷待訪錄. Taipei 臺北: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局 (Sibu beiyao edition).

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Zongxi 黃宗羲, and Quan Zuwang 全祖望. 1965. Song-Yuan Case Studies 宋元學案. Taipei 臺北: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局 (Sibu beiyao edition).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutton, Eric L. 2000. “Does Xunzi Have a Consistent Theory of Human Nature?” In Kline and Ivanhoe (2000). (An essential work on Xunzi’s theory of human nature, developing a more coherent and charitable reading of Xunzi in response to several challenges.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutton, Eric L., trans. 2014. Xunzi: The Complete Text. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2000a. Confucian Moral Self Cultivation, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA.: Hackett. (One of a small handful of authoritative introductions to Confucianism and Neo-Confucianism. Ivanhoe includes chapters on Xunzi, Zhu Xi, Wang Yangming and Dai Zhen, and highlights important structural differences between their views.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2000b. “Human Nature and Moral Understanding in the Xunzi.” In Kline and Ivanhoe (2000). (This paper tackles the difficult problem of identifying the precise points of dispute between Mengzi and Xunzi on human nature, developing a helpful analogy between their views and two theories of language acquisition.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2002a. “Confucian Self Cultivation and Mengzi’s Notion of Extension.” In Liu and Ivanhoe (2002): 221–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2002b. Ethics in the Confucian Tradition: The Thought of Mengzi and Wang Yangming, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA.: Hackett. (An authoritative work on Wang Yangming. Highlights the ways in which Wang’s distinctive metaphysics and theories of moral agency depart from Mengzi’s.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2009. Readings from the Lu-Wang School of Neo-Confucianism. Cambridge: Hackett. (The only extended English translation of Lu Xiangshan. Also translates selections from the essays, letters, commentaries and poetry of Wang Yangming. The translations of both figures are more accurate and readable than Chan’s, cited above.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2015. “The Senses and Values of Oneness.” In The Philosophical Challenge from China, ed. Brian Bruya, 231–51. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jiao, Xun 焦循. 1987 (2007 reprint). The Correct Meanings of the Mengzi 孟子正義. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline, T.C., III. 2000. “Moral Agency and Motivation in the Xunzi.” In Kline and Ivanhoe (2000).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline, T.C., III, and Philip J. Ivanhoe, eds. 2000. Virtue, Nature, and Moral Agency in the Xunzi. Cambridge: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knoblock, John. 1988, 1990, 1994. Xunzi: A Translation and Study of the Complete Works, 3 vols. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legge, James. 1970. The Shoo King. Reprinted in Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, D.C. 劉殿爵, and F.C. Chen 陳方正, eds. 1996. A Concordance to the Xunzi 荀子逐字索引. Hong Kong: The Commercial Press 商務印書館.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Baonan 劉寶楠. 1965. The Correct Meanings of the Analects 論語正義. Taipei 臺北: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局 (Sibu beiyao edition).

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Xiusheng, and Philip J. Ivanhoe, eds. 2002. Essays on the Moral Philosophy of Mengzi. Cambridge, MA.: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lu, Xiangshan 陸象山. 1965. The Complete Works of [ Lu ] Xiangshan 象山全集. Taipei 臺北: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局 (Sibu beiyao edition). (A Song dynasty Neo-Confucian philosopher. Also an important interlocutor and critic of Zhu Xi.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Makeham, John. 2003. Transmitters and Creators: Chinese Commentators and Commentaries on the Analects (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Asian Center).

    Google Scholar 

  • Makeham, John, ed. 2010. Dao Companion to Neo-Confucian Philosophy. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marchal, Kai. 2010. “ Zuqian’s Political Philosophy.” In Makeham (2010).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nivison, David S. 1996. “Two Roots or One?” In The Ways of Confucianism, ed. Bryan W. Van Norden, 133–48. Chicago: Open Court Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nylan, Michael and Thomas A. Wilson. 2010. Lives of Confucius: Civilization’s Greatest Sage Through the Ages. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shun, Kwong-loi. 2010. “Zhu Xi’s Moral Psychology.” In Makeham (2010).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, Aaron. 2003. “Aspects of Xunzi’s Engagement with Early Daoism.” Philosophy East and West 53(1): 87–129. (A helpful study of surprising points of overlap and influence between early Daoism and Xunzi, with substantial space devoted to the epistemic virtues discussed in the present chapter.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiwald, Justin. 2010. “Dai Zhen on Human Nature and Moral Cultivation.” In Makeham (2010).

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiwald, Justin. 2011a. Review of Sagehood: The Contemporary Significance of Neo-Confucian Philosophy. Dao 10(2): 231–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tiwald, Justin. 2011b. “Reply to Stephen Angle.” Dao 10(2): 241–43. (My contribution to a debate with Stephen C. Angle about the proper translation of li 理.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiwald, Justin. 2011c. “Sympathy and Perspective-Taking in Confucian Ethics.” Philosophy Compass 6(10): 663–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tiwald, Justin. 2012. “Xunzi on Moral Expertise.” Dao 11(2): 275–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tiwald, Justin, and Bryan W. Van Norden, eds. 2014. Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy: Han Dynasty to the 20th Century. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Norden, Bryan W. 2007. Virtue Ethics and Consequentialism in Early Chinese Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Norden, Bryan W., trans. 2008. Mengzi: With Selections from Traditional Commentaries. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Yangming 王陽明. 2000. “A Record for Practice” 傳習錄. In An Extended Commentary on A Record for Practice 傳習錄注疏, ed. Deng Aimin 鄧艾民. Jilong 基隆: Fayan chubanshe 法嚴出版社. (The most representative work of one of the two giants in Neo-Confucian philosophy.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1981. Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London: Fontana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xunzi 荀子. 1935. Collected Commentaries on Xunzi 荀子集解, ed. Wang Xianqian 王先謙. Taipei 臺北: Shijie shuju 世界書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yang, Xiong 楊雄. 1965. Words to Model Oneself On 法言. Taipei 臺北: Guangwen shuju 廣文書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhou, Dunyi 周敦頤. 1990. “Penetrating the Book of Changes” 通書. In The Collected Works of Zhou Dunyi 周敦頤集. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, Xi 朱熹, ed. 1965. “Misgivings about Master Hu’s Understanding of Words” 胡子知言疑義. In Huang and Quan (1965), vol. 3, juan 42, 3b–9a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, Xi 朱熹. 1986. Topically Arranged Conversations of Master Zhu, with Index Appended 朱子語類附所引, 8 vols., ed. Li Jingde 黎靖德. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局. (Several thousand pages of lessons and discussions with Zhu Xi, as recorded by his students.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, Xi 朱熹, ed. 1983 (reprinted in 2010). Collected Commentaries on the Four Books 中庸章句集注. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, Xi 朱熹, and Zuqian 呂祖謙, eds. 2008. Reflections on Things at Hand 近思錄. Zhengzhou 鄭州: Zhongzhou guji chubanshe 中州古藉出版社. (A collection of essays and short lessons selected from the work of four 11th century founders of orthodox Neo-Confucianism, treated as an introduction to the subject by many generations of Confucian scholars.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, Xi 朱熹. 2010. “Collected Commentaries on the Chuci” 楚辭集注. In The Collected Works of Zhu Xi 朱子全書, vol. 19. Shanghai 上海: Shanghai guji chubanshe 上海古籍出版社 and Anhui jiaoyu chubanshe 安徽教育出版社.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to Eric Hutton, Philip J. Ivanhoe, <Emphasis Type=”SmallCaps”>Xie</Emphasis> Xiaodong 謝曉東 and a generous anonymous reviewer for extensive and stimulating comments on earlier drafts of this chapter.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Justin Tiwald .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Tiwald, J. (2016). Xunzi Among the Chinese Neo-Confucians. In: Hutton, E. (eds) Dao Companion to the Philosophy of Xunzi. Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy, vol 7. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-7745-2_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics