Skip to main content

Part of the book series: International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine ((LIME,volume 62))

  • 429 Accesses

Abstract

Even if a person accepts that it is permissible to end one’s life earlier than if all efforts were made to preserve it, there is no guarantee that the person would also believe in an obligation to commit suicide. After all, an obligation to die would seem to remove the autonomy we want people to have when making end of life decisions. We would also have to be concerned that such a duty, if it existed, would be misused in order to eliminate the more vulnerable members of our society including the terminally or chronically ill and the elderly. In this chapter, I develop a Kantian argument for a suicide duty. In order to respect oneself and to preserve one’s moral life, at times it becomes mandatory to end one’s physical existence. Although a discordant position to take, I will show that such an obligation can be part of a very good life narrative, and can be done in a way that nurtures communities and caring relationships.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    She did argue that living wills and similar devices are mandatory.

  2. 2.

    See Mary Rose Barrington’s  (1980) “Apologia for Suicide” for another reasoned argument for suicide in these circumstances.

  3. 3.

    Battin provides an excellent comprehensive development of most arguments for and against suicide in The Death Debate: Ethical Issues in Suicide.

  4. 4.

    Scott Shershow argues that terms such as “dignity” and “sanctity” are imprecise words (Shershow 2014). I agree that the terms are inherently vague, but reject his deconstructivist approach in favor of a pragmatic one based on objective standards, as far as that is possible, and what works in the situation to achieve the goals of those involved in the conversation.

  5. 5.

    The utilitarian argument states that if the best thing a person can do is to suicide, then that is her duty. On the other hand, the justice arguments might be based on various distributive justice principles. In one, if a person has used more than her fair share of healthcare resources, then she has an obligation to refrain from using any more, which will passively end her life.

  6. 6.

    See Brassington (2006).Thomas De Quincy , for instance, argues that men have such a duty if the alternative is having their nature dishonored through corporal punishment (De Quincy 1856, 231).

  7. 7.

    According to Christine Overall, the taking of one’s own life does not respect life’s intrinsic value in the proper way (Overall 2003, 74–5).

  8. 8.

    Richard Brandt , among most others, claims “Kant was opposed to suicide in all circumstances.” (Brandt 1979, 466). Alan Soble , on the other hand, adopts the view that Kant endorsed suicide but was heartless and misogynistic as well. (Soble 2003, 1–2).

  9. 9.

    Some may wonder why PP is not being used in this argument. In fact it is; I will show that such suicides respect the intrinsic value of those things affected by the action and that it is something that at least one reasonable person would reasonably believe will likely maximize utility. Satisfying these two conditions makes the action morally right.

    What makes some suicides mandatory is that they are the only way an action can satisfy the Kantian QCI; therefore, I will spend more time developing this claim than showing RPU is satisfied.

  10. 10.

    I will not address Emile Durkheim’s claim that society for social purposes can impose a duty of suicide (2003). Instead, I will take it as a given that Kant’s claim that no one can bind a person to commit suicide is true (Kant 1979c, 150).

  11. 11.

    Kant’s position can be compared to that of Buddhists’ . “Buddhism sees death as not the end of life, but simply a transition; suicide is therefore no escape from anything.” (Becker 2000, 499).

  12. 12.

    Not everyone will agree with Kant’s claim that an innocent person commits moral suicide when he chooses to become a slave. Most people would probably agree that a slave is still a person, although owned by another.

  13. 13.

    For the purposes of space, I will not try to list and defend the required mental states. Rather, I will stipulate that there must be certain mental states, given Kant’s theory, but what they are is a question for another time.

  14. 14.

    Kant’s psychological theories are often primitive at best. He assumes a vast control over behavior that does not in reality exist, such as in cases of internal compulsion. The issue of internal compulsion and Kant’s inadequate psychology will be addressed in the section on psychotic sexual predators.

  15. 15.

    The fourth condition does not work well. In end of life decisions, I will argue later, it is wrong to burden others by requesting and using their assistance unless the agent cannot kill herself by herself. On these grounds, I contend that the first three conditions are sufficient when all three are met.

  16. 16.

    Kass argues vehemently against suicide on the grounds that people are unable to make free decisions. The illness and its consequences are too coercive to allow for free choice (Kass 1995, 228).

  17. 17.

    Feldman states that actively pursuing death can be a rational action (Feldman 1992, 222). Marilyn Bennett claims it is rational to die before a loss accrues (Bennett 2000, 49–50).

  18. 18.

    Menzel expands Hardwig’s scope to include others burdened by the continued life. If there is a high burden placed upon others and a low prospective given to the individual for staying alive, then according to Menzel, there is an obligation to die (Menzel 2000, 97).

  19. 19.

    The combination of reason and emotion recognizes that reasonable decisions, which are part rational and part non-rational, are how people actually make ethical choices. An overly rational approach is impossible; no one would ever be able to choose one alternative over another. On the other hand, an overemotional response ignores necessary evidence.

  20. 20.

    One arguable legal method of killing oneself is the intentional starvation of the individual. The greatest benefit to this course of action is the medical assistance and advice the individual would have during the process, which not only makes it less violent and more effective, but also creates a caring, supportive atmosphere.

  21. 21.

    Dworkin’s (1995) position contradicts Callahan’s claim that no one can place death’s power in another’s hands (Callahan 2001b, 224).

  22. 22.

    This issue has been convincingly addressed by Rebecca Dresser (1989, 1995) and John A. Roberston (1991).

  23. 23.

    Even if there is life after death and the entity that lives on is identical to the person, not killing the person’s body shows no disrespect to the person. The independent departed is no longer a part of the dyad; hence, it has no right to decide the disposition of the body. What is done to the body, therefore, is not done to the person.

  24. 24.

    Claiming that the person’s continued intrinsic value as a person in her various forms overcomes the loss caused by the disrespect she shows to herself by not committing suicide does little to defeat a duty to kill oneself. Considering only the person as psychological person’s and moral agent’s intrinsic values, then a bare state of affairs in which she exists has more worth than a bare state of affairs in which she does not. To respect intrinsic value and to try to bring about the outcome that reasonably will produce the best outcome, the bare state of affairs in which the person exists is preferable to the alternative. This is a simplified view that does not reflect the much more complex reality of which the individual is part.

    When considering the overall psychological and embedded person, the Practical Principle actually establishes that suicide is morally right in the circumstances. Moreover, since it is the one alternative likely to satisfy the Practical Principle in many situations, it becomes a duty for them.

  25. 25.

    Davis (1999, 118).

  26. 26.

    There is a debate over whether euthanasia has led to a slippery slope. On one side, it is claimed that since euthanasia was legalized in the Netherlands , there does not appear to be a slippery slope developing, although there is a contention about what euthanasia is and what it is not (Battin et al. 2007; Norwood et al. 2009) Rietjens et al. 2009). On the other, it is claimed that there are a large number of euthanasia cases left unreported (900 people annually are euthanized without asking for it), and that euthanasia is being used impermissibly for persons and moral subjects who are not terminally ill (Pereira 2011). I contend that euthanasia would occur regardless of its legal standing, and it is far better to regulate it than to allow it to remain hidden, and therefore open the door to far more abuse than already may exist.

  27. 27.

    The negative stigma might affect available statistics on suicide because of the desire for survivors to hide what happened from outside judgment (Gorowitz 1975, 213). Even today, people tend to be reluctant to put the cause of death as suicide in newspaper obituaries or discuss how the person died.

  28. 28.

    A more detailed discussion of appropriate emotional states appears in an earlier chapter.

  29. 29.

    See Altman’s (2011) and Perry’s (2007) articles.

  30. 30.

    This is actually Kant’s (1993) argument for why it is rational to believe God exists (See the Critique of Practical Reason. Part I, Bk. II, Chap. V).

  31. 31.

    Even if the Kantian argument is insufficient to prove a duty to die, at the very least it shows suicide in these situations is morally permissible and should be legally permitted.

References

  • Altman, M.C. 2011. Kant and applied ethics: The uses and limits of Kant’s practical philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez, A. 1998. The history of suicide. In Last rights: Assisted suicide and euthanasia debated, ed. M.M. Uhlmann, 57–74. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alzheimer’s Association. 2013. Alzheimer’s disease facts and figures. http://www.alz.org/downloads/facts_figures_2013.pdf. Accessed 30 Aug 2014.

  • Battin, M. 1994. The least worst death. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battin, M.P. 1996. The death debate: Ethical issues in suicide. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battin, M., et al. 2007. Legal physician-assisted dying in Oregon and the Netherlands: Evidence concerning the impact on patients in ‘vulnerable’ groups. Journal of Medical Ethics 33: 591–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrington, M.R. 1980. Apologia for suicide. In suicide, ed. M.P. Battin, and D.J. Mayo, 90–103. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T.L. 1986. Suicide. In Matters of life and death, ed. Tom Regan, 77–124. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, C.B. 2000. Buddhist views of suicide and euthanasia. In Living well, ed. Steven Luper, 498–500. Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, G. 2014. Goodbye and good luck! http://deadatnoon.com/index.html. Accessed 15 Feb 2015.

  • Bennett, M. 2000. Do we have a duty to die? In Is there a duty to die?, ed. J.M. Humber, and R.F. Almeder, 41–60. Totowa: Humana Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R. 1979. The morality and rationality of suicide. In Moral problems: A collection of philosophical essays, 3rd edition, ed. J. Rachels, 460–89. New York: Harper & Row, Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brassington, I. 2006. Killing people: What Kant could have said about suicide and euthanasia but did not. Journal of Medical Ethics 32: 571–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callahan, D. 2001a. Terminating life-sustaining treatment of the demented. In Bioethics, ed. J. Harris, 93–108. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callahan, D. 2001b. When self-determination runs amok. In Ethics at the end of life, ed. R. Borgen, 223–228. Belmont: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooley, D. 2006. Crimina carnis and morally obligatory suicide. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 97: 327–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooley, D. 2007. A Kantian moral duty for the soon to be demented to commit suicide. American Journal of Bioethics 76: 37–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooley, D. 2013. A Kantian care ethics suicide duty. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 36: 366–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, D. 1998. Why suicide is like contraception. In Physician assisted suicide, ed. M.P. Battin, R. Rhodes, and A. Silver, 113–122. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, D. 1999. Rational suicide and predictive genetic testing. The Journal of Clinical Ethics, Winter: 316–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Quincy, T. 1856. Essays in philosophy. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowbiggin, I. 2005. A concise history of euthanasia. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefeld Publishers Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dresser, R. 1995. Dworkin on dementia—elegant theory, questionable policy. Hastings Center Report 25(6): 32–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dresser, R. 1989. Advance directives, self-determination, and personal identity. In Advance directives in medicine, ed. C. Hackler, R. Moseley, and D.E. Vawter, 155–170. New York:Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. 2003. Altruistic suicide. http://www.suicidereferencelibrary.com/28.html. Accessed 30 Aug 2014.

  • Dworkin, R. 1995. Life is sacred. In Arguing Euthanasia, ed. J.D. Moreno, 246–251. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt Jr, H.T. 1995. Fashioning an ethic for life and death in a post-modern society. In Arguing Euthanasia, ed. J.D. Moreno, 42–50. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fairbairn, J.G. 1995. Contemplating suicide: The language and ethics of self harm. New Fetter Lane: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. 1992. Confrontations with the reaper. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorowitz, K. 1975. Case registers. In A handbook for the study of suicide, ed. S. Perlin, 213–226. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardwig, J. 1997. Is there a duty to die? Hastings Center Report 21(2): 32–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1964. Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. Trans. H.J. Paton. New York: Harper & Row, Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I.1979a. Care for one’s life. In Lectures on ethics, trans. Louis Infield, 154–157. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I.1979b. Crimina carnis. In Lectures on ethics, trans. Louis Infield, 169–171. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1979c. Suicide. In Lectures on ethics, trans. Louis Infield, 148–54. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1993. Critique of Practical Reason. Trans. Lewis White Beck. New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1996. The metaphysics of morals. Trans. M. Gregory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kass, L.R. 1995. Death with dignity and the sanctity of life. In Arguing euthanasia, ed. J.D. Moreno, 211–236. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. 1975. Negativities: The limits of life. Columbus: Charles E. Merrill Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, P.T. 2000. The nature, scope, and implications of a personal moral duty to die. In Is there a duty to die?, ed. J.M. Humber, and R.F. Almeder, 95–114. Totowa: Humana Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1972. Utilitarianism, on liberty and considerations on representative government. Ed. H.B. Acton. London: J. M. Dent & Sons, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mullett, S. 1988. Shifting perspectives: A new approach to ethics. In Feminist perspectives, ed. L. Code, S. Mullett, and C. Overall, 109–126. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Narveson, J. 2000. Is there a duty to die? In Is there a duty to die?, ed. J.M. Humber, and R.F. Almeder, 23–40. Totowa: Humana Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Norwood, F., G. Kimsma, and M.P. Battin. 2009. Vulnerability and the ‘slippery slope’ at the end-of-life: A qualitative study of euthanasia, general practice and home death in The Netherlands. Family Practice 26(6): 472–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overall, C. 2003. Aging, death, and human longevity. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereira, J. 2011. Legalizing euthanasia or assisted suicide: The illusion of safeguards and controls. Current Oncology 18(2): e38–e45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pence, G. 2007. The elements of bioethics. Boston: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, C. 2007. Suicide fails to pass the categorical imperative. American Journal of Bioethics 76: 51–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prado, G.C. 2008. Choosing to die: Elective death and multiculturalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rabins, P.V. 2007. Can suicide be a rational and ethical act in persons with early or pre-dementia? American Journal of Bioethics 76: 47–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietjens, J.A.C., P.J. van der Maas, B.D. Onwuteaka-Philipsen, et al. 2009. Two decades of research on euthanasia from the Netherlands. What have we learnt and what questions remain? Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 6(3): 271–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rhodes, R. 2007. A Kantian duty to commit suicide and its implications for bioethics. American Journal of Bioethics 76: 45–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberston, J.A. 1991. Second thoughts on living wills. Hastings Center Report 21(6): 6–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. 1975. History. In A handbook for the study of suicide, ed. S. Perlin, 3–29. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Outomuro, D. 2007. Morality of suicide in dementia. American Journal of Bioethics 7(6): 64–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shershow, S.C. 2014. Deconstructing dignity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soble, A. 2003. Kant and sexual perversion. The Monist 86(1): 55–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tong, R. 2000. Duty to die. In Is there a duty to die?, ed. J.M. Humber, and R.F. Almeder, 133–158. Totowa: Humana Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zizek, S. 2000. The fragile absolute. New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dennis R. Cooley .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Cooley, D.R. (2015). A Duty to Suicide. In: Death’s Values and Obligations: A Pragmatic Framework. International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine, vol 62. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-7264-8_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics