Skip to main content

Relativistic Classical and Quantum Mechanics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Relativistic Quantum Mechanics

Part of the book series: Fundamental Theories of Physics ((FTPH,volume 180))

  • 2870 Accesses

Abstract

To develop the foundations of a manifestly covariant mechanics, we must first examine the Einstein notion of time and its physical meaning. We will then be in a position to introduce the relativistic quantum theory developed by Stueckelberg (1941) and Horwitz and Piron (1973). We describe in this chapter a simple and conceptual understanding of the Newton-Wigner problem (Newton 1949) presented above, a rigorous basis for the energy time uncertainty relation, as well as a simple explanation of the Landau-Peierls (Landau 1931) uncertainty relation between momentum and time. These applications provide a good basis for understanding the basic ideas of the relativistic quantum theory. Schieve and Trump (1999) have discussed at some length the associated manifestly covariant classical theory, but some basic aspects will be discussed here as well.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Note that both time intervals, as well as space intervals, must be thought of as measured by geodesic projection (e.g. Weinberg 1972) since clocks and rulers brought to the location of the events would suffer distortion due to the gravitational field as well.

  2. 2.

    This discussion is fundamental in understanding the essential distinction between the measured time of Einstein, which plays the role of a coordinate of a physical event, and the underlying absolute time \(\tau \) governing the dynamical processes of evolution.

  3. 3.

    In Galilean mechanics, due to the existence of a cohomology in the Lie algebra of the Galilean group, a definite value must be assigned to the value of the mass to achieve an irreducible representation (Sudarshan 1974). The Poincaré group does not have such a cohomology, and thus admits the full generality of the Stueckelberg theory. We discuss the Galilean limit in more detail in Chap. 10.

  4. 4.

    An alternative covariant structure for a relativistic quantum theory, the so-called constraint mechanics, discussed in Appendix A of this chapter, based on the constraint theory developed by Dirac (1966) to deal with the quantization of gravity and gauge fields, extensively studied by Sudarshan et al. (1981a), Rohrlich (1981) and others (Llosa 1982), does have a mechanism for enforcing the asymptotic return of a particle to a given mass shell. This theory, however, necessarily makes use of a system of constraints of the first class (Itzykson 1980), a condition that makes the construction of a useful quantum theory very difficult (Horwitz 1982).

  5. 5.

    As Van Hove (1951) has pointed out, this correspondence is not applicable for higher order polynomials; both the Poisson bracket and the commutators are distributive in the Leibniz sense, but in the quantum case the algebra is not commutative, and it is not always possible to regroup factors as in the classical, commutative, case. The problem of consistent quantization has been studied under the name “geometric quantization” (Kostant 1970).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lawrence P. Horwitz .

Appendix A

Appendix A

We describe here the basic ideas of the so-called constraint theory formulation of a many particle (many event) relativistic mechanics . In this theory, describing the positions \(\{ x^\mu _i\}\), and momenta \(\{p^\mu _i\}\) for \(i=1,2,3,\ldots ,N\) of the particles, a constraint is defined for each of the particles of the form (we use the metric \((-,+,+,+)\))

$$\begin{aligned} K_i = {p^\mu }_i {p_\mu }_i +m_i^2 + \phi _i(x,p), \end{aligned}$$
(2.67)

where, on the constraint hypersurface \(K_i \approx 0\), the \(\phi _i(x,p)\) are functions of all the x’s and p’s, and the \(\{m_i\}\) are the given masses of the particles. This set of N constraints restricts the motion to an N dimensional hypersurface in the 8N dimensional phase space.

The “first class” constraints \(K_i\) may act as generators of motion under Poisson bracket action (e.g. Itzyson 1980), thus defining the infinitesimal variations with respect to the corresponding parameters \(\tau _i\) of the infinitesimal transformations of the coordinates and momenta by

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} {dx_i \over d \tau _i}&= i \{ K_i, x_i\}_{PB} \\ {dp_i \over d \tau _i}&= i \{ K_i, p_i\}_{PB}, \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(2.68)

providing a set of first order equations describing the motion on this hypersurface. This manifestly covariant formalism has the advantage that one may assume the interaction terms \(\phi _i\) vanish asymptotically when the particles are far apart; the constraint conditions then enforce the particles to lie on mass shell (\({p^\mu }_i {p_\mu }_i +m_i^2 =0\)).

In order to construct a world line for the system on the range of these motions, one generally introduces another set of \(N-1\) constraints, called second class constraints, forming surfaces with intersection along a line on the N dimensional hypersurface, and an Nth constraint which cuts this line and is a function of a single parameter \(\tau \), thus describing motion along this world line (Sudarshan 1981a). It is possible, however, to define these constraints in another way, by constructing a Hamiltonian of the form (Rohrlich 1981)

$$\begin{aligned} K = \Sigma _i \omega _i (x,p) K_i. \end{aligned}$$
(2.69)

The Poisson bracket of this Hamiltonian with any observable \( \mathcal{O}( x,p)\) then forms a linear combination

$$\begin{aligned} {d\mathcal{O} \over d\tau } = \Sigma _i \omega _i {d \mathcal{O} \over d\tau _i}, \end{aligned}$$
(2.70)

where we have taken into account that the \(K_i\) vanish on the constraint hypersurface; the \(\omega _i\) are then identified with \(d\tau _i /d\tau \), with the \(\tau _i\) considered as functions of the overall evolution parameter \(\tau \).

Although this approach is very elegant on a classical level, there are some difficulties in passing to the quantum theory. The condition \(K_i = 0\) poses a difficult problem since, in general, the \(K_i\) have continuous spectrum, and the eigenstates would lie outside the Hilbert space. This problem can be treated by defining N Schrödinger type equations of the form (as for the treatment of cases with states in the continuous spectrum in the nonrelativistic theory)

$$\begin{aligned} i {\partial \psi _{\tau _1,\tau _2, \dots } \over \partial \tau _i} = K_i \psi _{\tau _1,\tau _2, \dots } \end{aligned}$$
(2.71)

but the combination \(\Sigma _i {\omega _i} (x,p) K_i\) would, in general, not be Hermitian. The symmetric product with the \(\omega _i\)’s would not be useful, since the functions \(\omega _i\) have no well-defined action on \(\psi _{\tau _1,\tau _2, \dots }\). Nevertheless, Rohrlich and the author succeeded in formulating a viable scattering theory in this framework (see references under Llosa 1982).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Horwitz, L.P. (2015). Relativistic Classical and Quantum Mechanics. In: Relativistic Quantum Mechanics. Fundamental Theories of Physics, vol 180. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-7261-7_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics