Skip to main content

Music as an Apprenticeship for Life: John Dewey on the Art of Living

  • Chapter
Art's Teachings, Teaching's Art

Part of the book series: Contemporary Philosophies and Theories in Education ((COPT,volume 8))

  • 1184 Accesses

Abstract

Megan J. Laverty’s paper focuses on rhythm or the patterned and recurrent alternation of sound and silence that we find in music and its relation to education. She considers the broader existential significance of this phenomenon using Dewey’s aesthetic philosophy. Laverty argues that if Dewey is right that (a) music exemplifies artfulness and (b) to live well is to live artfully, then an education in music—formal and informal—constitutes an education in how to live well. Artfulness, according to Dewey, involves, the intelligent harmonizing of the precarious, novel and irregular with the settled, assured and uniform. Laverty explains what Dewey means by intelligent harmonization and contrasts it with those occasions when individuals act from enforced necessity, routine or blind impulse. Laverty offers an intrinsic justification for arts education that focuses on a quality not previously highlighted by Maxine Greene and others. Clearly humanist, Laverty thereby aligns Greene with other post-humanist contributions by focusing on an iterative process constitutive of our material condition. The aim, as with so much of post-humanism, is not to control or direct this process in the interest of a telos, but to vibrate possibility.

A note of music gains significance from the silence on either side.

Anne Morrow Lindbergh

I sat by the window, alternating

my first lesson in reading with

watching time pass, my introduction to

philosophy and religion.

Louise Glück

An abridged version of this chapter was presented as an invited keynote presentation at the International Philosophy of Music Education Biennial Conference, Teachers College, Columbia University, June 6, 2013. I am grateful to the participants at that conference for their comments. I would also like to gratefully acknowledge the students who participated in a doctoral seminar on John Dewey’s philosophy. Conversations with Guillermo Marini and Jason Wozniak have been particularly instructive.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Noel Carroll argues that Dewey’s definition of an aesthetic experience is not sufficiently broad to include such works that do not possess such qualitative unity, such as John Cage’s 4’33’. I agree with David Hildebrand who argues, following Richard Shusterman, that “While contemporary artworks may be filled with ‘jarring fragmentation and incoherencies’ (or even silence), such aspects must be understood not simply in relation to the artwork as an isolated object/event, but to the ‘more complex forms of coherence’ that arise ‘within a larger coherent totality of meaning’ in the experienced situation that frames the work.” (157–158) – cited in Felicia E. Kruse, “Temporality in Musical Meaning: A Peircean/Deweyan Semiotic Approach”, The Pluralist, 6.3. (2011), p. 57.

  2. 2.

    Copland, 27–28, cited in Felicia E., Kruse, Semiotic Approach, The Pluralist 6.3 (2011), 55.

  3. 3.

    For a discussion of the role of repetition in marriage see Søren Kierkegaard, Either/Or, Vol. II, ed. And trans. Howard and Edna Hong (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), 138–144.

  4. 4.

    For a related critique of consumerism that also draws on aesthetics, see René V. Arcilla (2011) Mediumism: A Philosophical Reconstruction of Modernism for Existential Learning, New York, SUNY, Chapter Five, pp. 65–82.

Bibliography

  • Alexander, T. (1987). John Dewey’s theory of art, experience and nature. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arcilla, R. V. (2010). Mediumism: A philosophical reconstruction for existential learning. New York: State University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, W. (1986). The work of art in the age of mechanical reproduction. In Illuminations. New York: Shocken Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boon, I. E. T. Toward a useful synthesis of Deweyan pragmatism and music education. Visions of Research in Music Education, 14. Retrieved from http://www-usr.rider.edu/~vrme/

  • Brewer, T. (2009). The retrieval of ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, N. (2001). Four concepts of aesthetic experience. In Beyond aesthetics: Philosophical essays (pp. 41–61). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carson, A. (1999). The idea of a university (After John Henry Newman). The Threepenny Review, 78, 6–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1984). Qualitative thought. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), The later works, 1925–1953. Essays, the sources of a science of education, individualism, old and new, and construction and criticism (Vol. 5: 1929–1930, pp. 243–262). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1986). How we think. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), The later works, 1925–1953 (Vol. 8: 1933). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (2008). Experience and nature. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), Later works (Vol. 1). 1925. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (2008). Art as experience. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), The later works, 1925–1953 (Vol. 10: 1934). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaita, R. (1991). Good and evil: An absolute conception. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaita, R. To civilize the city? Meanjin. http://meanjin.com.au/articles/post/to-civilise-the-city/

  • Garrison, J. (1997). Dewey and Eros: Wisdom and desire in the art of teaching. New York: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granger, D. (2006). John Dewey, Robert Pirsig, and the art of living. London: Palgrave, Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, M. (1965/2007). The public school and the private vision: A search for America in education and literature. New York: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, M. (1978). Landscapes of learning. New York: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, M. (2001). Variations on a Blue Guitar: The Lincoln Center Institute Lectures on Aesthetic Education. New York: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higgins, C. (2011). The good life of teaching: An ethics of professional practice. London: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, P. W. (1998). John Dewey and the lessons of art. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kruse, F. E. (2011). Temporality in musical meaning: A Peircean/Deweyan semiotic approach. The Pluralist, 6(3), 50–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1981). After virtue. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nehamas, A. (2004). Art, interpretation, and the rest of life. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 78(2), 25–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, D. (1998). Cultivating the imagination in music education: John Dewey’s theory of imagination and its relation to the Chicago Laboratory School. Educational Theory, 48(2), 193–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shiraishi, F. (1995). Music education at the Dewey School 1896–1904. The Bulletin of Historical Research in Music Education, 17(1), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westerlund, H. (2003). Reconsidering aesthetic experience in praxial music education. Philosophy of Music Education Review, 11(1), 45–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westerlund, H. (2008). Justifying music education: View from here-and-now value experience. Philosophy of Music Education Review, 16(1), 80–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winner, E., & Cooper, M. (2000). Mute those claims: No evidence (yet) for a causal link between arts study and academic achievement. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 34(3&4), 11–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winner, E., & Hetland, L. (2000). The arts in education: Evaluating the evidence for a causal link. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 34(3&4), Special Issue: The Arts and Academic Achievement; What the Evidence Shows, 3–10.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Megan J. Laverty .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Laverty, M.J. (2015). Music as an Apprenticeship for Life: John Dewey on the Art of Living. In: Lewis, T., Laverty, M. (eds) Art's Teachings, Teaching's Art. Contemporary Philosophies and Theories in Education, vol 8. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-7191-7_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics