Skip to main content
  • 42 Accesses

Abstract

Analogy, symbolism and analogia fidei are three methods whereby Aquinas, Tillich and Barth respectively seek to provide a tool capable of giving an adequate interpretation of the God-creature relation and a justification for theological language. Analogy, symbolism and analogia fidei are different answers to the same problem. The problem is the meaning of words applied to God and to creatures. If our words mean exactly the same thing when applied to God and to creatures, then God’s transcendence is eliminated: God ceases to be God in order to be a creature or vice versa. On the other hand, if our words bear an altogether different meaning when applied to God, then God’s immanence is obscured: man is no longer in a position to know God.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic (New York: Dover), p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Reprinted in Philosophy and Psycho-Analysis (Oxford 1953), pp. 149–168.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid. p. 156.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid. p. 154. I am indebted to Professor M. J. Charlesworth for the summary of Wisdom’s, Smart’s, Hare’s and Crombie’s articles. See M. J. Charlesworth, “Linguistic Analysis and God,” International Philosophical Quarterly 1961, pp. 144–163.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ed. A. Flew and A. MacIntyre (London: S.C.M. Press, 1955).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid. p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  7. M. J. Charlesworth, “Linguistic Analysis and God,” in International Philosophical Quarterly 1961, p. 149. See also the following pages where Charlesworth makes a very pointed critique of Smart’s argument. Cfr. Charlesworth, Philosophy and Linguistic Analysis (Pittsburgh: Duquesne Univ., 1959), pp. 134–135 for the critique of Ayer on this same point.

    Google Scholar 

  8. M. J. Charlesworth, “Linguistic Analysis and God,” in International Philosophical Quarterly 1961, p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Even more manifest is the danger of behaviourism in R.B. Braithwaite’s theory. See especially An Empiricist’s View of the Nature of Religious Belief (Cambridge University, 1955).

    Google Scholar 

  10. I. T. Ramsey, Religious Language: an Empirical Placing of Theological Phrases (London: S.C.M. Press, 1957);

    Google Scholar 

  11. I. M. Crombie. “The Possibility of Theological Statements,” in Faith and Logic, ed. by Mitchell (London 1957)

    Google Scholar 

  12. B. G. Mitchell, Faith and Logic; M. Forster, “Contemporary British Philosophy and Christian Belie,” in Cross Currents 1960, pp. 375–385.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Faith and Logic, ed. B. Mitchell (London 1957).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid. p. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid. p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  16. This is a view shared by Anglican theologians in general. 6 Ibid. p. 57.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  18. M.J. Charlesworth, Linguistic Analysis and God, in “International Philosophical Quarterly” 1961, pp. 163–164.

    Google Scholar 

  19. The article has first appeared in The Christian Scholar (Fall 1960) and was, then, reprinted by Cross Currents 1960, pp. 375–385.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cross Currents 1960, p. 383.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid. p. 383.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid. p. 384.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid. p. 385.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid. p. 385.

    Google Scholar 

  25. The reason for the restriction of our analysis to theological language is that this has been so far the scope of our study, since in the previous chapters we have been concerned with the meaning of theological language in Catholic and Protestant theology.

    Google Scholar 

  26. M. J. Scheeben, The Mysteries of Christianity, transl. G. Vollert, (London-St. Louis: Herder, 1947), pp. 752–753.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Elsewhere we have put the same thing this way: “Le parole adoperate per significare i concetti teologici sono le parole ordinarie, le quali, però, una volta che la trasfigurazione analogica è stata compiuta, vengono ad acquistare un significato nuovo. Tuttavia dato che esse continuano a ritenere anche quello vecchio, l’uomo versa nel constante pericolo di lasciarle ricadere in esso. Quando questo awiene, le parole teologiche diventano vuote, senza senso. Fino a quando però il vecchio senso (e l’uomo vecchio) non ha il soprawento, esse conservano un significato, che, pure essendo misterioso (perchè la fede non dissipa tutti i veli del mistero), ha certamente valore teoretico non solamente emotivo (Positivismo logico, analisi linguistica e teologia, in Divus Thomas, 1961, p. 306).

    Google Scholar 

  28. “Hoc enim est ultimum ad quod pertingere possumus circa cognitionem divinam in hac vita, quod Deus est supra omne id quod a nobis cogitari potest.” (Aquinas, In Divinis Nominibus I, Lect. 3, no 83.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1963 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mondin, B. (1963). The Meaning of Theological Language. In: The Principle of Analogy in Protestant and Catholic Theology. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-6574-9_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-6574-9_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-017-6448-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-6574-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics