Skip to main content

Formal logic as apophantic analytics

  • Chapter
  • 130 Accesses

Abstract

From our general explanations it is already understandable that, as historically the first part of a systematically executed logic, Aristotelian analytics arose, a first commencement of a logic of theoretical formations. Within the limits imposed by focusing on this theme, it was a “formallogic in a particular sense; though, even as that, it did not attain the full purity and breadth prescribed by its essence. In a survey of the (always materially determinate) judgments of life and science, the most universal groupings of judgments according to types, the perfect likenesses of form among judgments pertaining even to heterogeneous provinces, immediately came to the fore. Aristotle was the first to bring out the idea of form which was to determine the fundamental sense of a “formal logic”, as we understand such a discipline today and as Leibniz already understood it in effecting his synthesis of formal logic (as apophantic) and formal analysis to make the unity of a mathesis universalis. Aristotle was the first, we may say, to execute in the apophantic sphere — the sphere of assertive statements (“judgments” in the sense expressed by the word in traditional logic) — that “formalization” or algebraization which makes its appearance in modern algebra with Vieta and distinguishes subsequent formal “analysis” from all material mathematical disciplines (geometry, mechanics, and the rest). In the materially determinate statements taken as examples, Aristotle substituted algebraic letters for the words (terms) indicating the material: that which is spoken about in the statements, that which determines judgments as/judgments relating to divers material provinces or single matters. As concerning the sense, this implied that he substituted the moment “anything whatever” for each materially filled “core” in the judgments, while the remaining judgment-moments were held fast as moments of form, moments that persist without change when one changes the relatedness of the given judgment to matters — or interchanges judgments pertaining to different material spheres — at pleasure. With this taking of the materially filled cores as indeterminate optional affairs — lingually, as indeterminate terms, S, p, and the like — the exemplificative determinate judgment becomes converted into the universal and pure form-idea: the pure concept of any judgment whatever that has, as the case may be, the determinate judgment-form “S is p”, the form “If S is p, then Q is r, or the like.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   74.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Author’s note: Cf. Appendix I, pp. 294 ff., infra.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Author’s note: See Martin Heidegger, Die Kategorien- undBedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus [Duns Scotus’s Theory of Categories and Signification (Tübingen, 1916)], particularly p. 34. Also Martin Grabmann, “Die Entwicklung der mittelalterlichen Sprachlogik [The Development of Medieval Linguistic Logic] (Tractatus de modis significandi)”, Philosophisches Jahrbuch der Görresgesellschaft, 1922, pp. 121ff. and 199ff., and the same article, revised and expanded, in Grabmann, Mittelalterliches Geistesleben: Abhandlungen zur Geschichte der Scholastik und Mystik, München, 1926. On the Grammatica speculativa, previously attributed to Duns Scotus, as in fact a work by Thomas of Erfurt, see op. cit., particularly pp. 118–125.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Author’s note: For the thorough legitimation of the idea of this “grammar of pure logic” see Logische Untersuchungen, II. Bd., I. Teil, Abschnitt IV. [Cf. Farber, op. cit., Chap. XI, pp. 313–332.]

    Google Scholar 

  4. Translator’s note: For a clarification of the terms “consequence-logic” and “logic of non-contradiction” see Appendix III, § I, pp. 330–334, infra.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Author’s note: Cf. Ideen, pp. 247f. [English translation, pp. 335ff.]

    Google Scholar 

  6. Author’s note: On this whole exposition cf. Appendix II, [pp. 313–329, infra].

    Google Scholar 

  7. Author’s note: To speak of a “limit” rather than an idea of clarity would not always be appropriate, though limit is the word that first comes to mind. Not always should one think of something like a limes. Perfect evidence of external experience, for example, is a regulative idea in the Kantian sense. External experience is, a priori, never a perfect giving of anything itself; but, as long as external experience goes on with consistent harmony, it bears within itself, as an intentional implication, the idea of an infinite self-contained system of possible experiences that we, starting from de facto experience, could have gone through, or could go through now or in the future, — experiences such that, as harmonious continuations of de facto experience, they would have shown (or would show) what the physical thing is, “in and of itself”, besides what it has already shown itself to be. As the correlate of this phenomenologically clarifiable infinite anticipation (which, as an infinite anticipation, has an evidence of its own) the physical thing existing in itself is, for its part, an idea, one that rightly guides the thinking done in natural science and enables such thinking to progress by degrees of approximation, each having its relative evidence. For our purposes we can content ourselves with a crude initial description of “clarity”. (On the concept of the physical thing as an idea in the Kantian sense, cf. Ideen, pp. 390ff., [English translation pp. 411ff.].)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Author’s note: See § 14, [pp. 53–55, supra].

    Google Scholar 

  9. Translator’s note: Cf. Appendix III, § 4, pp. 338–340, infra.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Translator’s note: It may be that the intent of this paragraph would be indicated less misleadingly as follows.

    Google Scholar 

  11. A judgment in which two mutually contradictory judgments are conjoined is not possible as a judgment proper; it cannot become given as a possible judgment in distinct evidence; it does not have ideal “mathematical existence”. But at least one of any two mutually contradictory judgments has such “existence”; at least one of them can become given as a possible judgment in distinct evidence.

    Google Scholar 

  12. For a justification of the main changes involved in this rendering, see § 14, supra, the first sentence in the fourth paragraph.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Translator’s note: Cf. § 16 c, p. 62, note, supra.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1969 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Husserl, E. (1969). Formal logic as apophantic analytics. In: Formal and Transcendental Logic. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-4900-8_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-4900-8_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-017-4638-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-4900-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics